Switch to: References

Citations of:

Essays on educators

Boston: Allen & Unwin (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Ritual, Imitation and Education in R. S. Peters.Bryan R. Warnick - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):57-74.
    This article reconstructs R. S. Peters' underlying theory of ritual in education, highlighting his proposed link between ritual and the imitation of teachers. Rituals set the stage for the imitation of teachers and they invite students to experience practices whose value is not easily discernable from the outside. For Peters, rituals facilitate the transmission of values across time, create unity in schools, and affirm authority relations. There is a tension, however, between this view of ritual and imitation, on the one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What should Educational Institutions be for?James MacAllister - 2016 - British Journal of Educational Studies 64 (3):375-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Research in Vocational Education and Training.Christopher Winch - 2012 - British Journal of Educational Studies 60 (1):53-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards an educationally meaningful curriculum: Epistemic holism and knowledge integration revisited.David Carr - 2007 - British Journal of Educational Studies 55 (1):3-20.
    Despite the 'progressive' influence of the English Plowden Report and Scottish Primary Memorandum on British primary curricula from the 1960s onwards, secondary education has generally continued to follow a more traditional subject-centred route and post-war educational theorists have not generally been favourably inclined to other than subject-based modes of curriculum planning and organisation. However, in the light of current curriculum reviews on both sides of the Scottish border-callingfor more educationally meaningful curricula-the perennial issue of how school knowledge might best be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Place of Philosophy in the Training of Teachers: Peters revisited.John A. Clark - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):128-141.
    In 1964, Richard Peters examined the place of philosophy in the training of teachers. He considered three things: Why should philosophy of education be included in the training of teachers; What portion of philosophy of education should be included; How should philosophy be taught to those training to be teachers. This article explores the context of the time when Peters set out his views, describes philosophy of education at the London Institute of Education at one period in Peters? time there, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Revolutions in English Philosophy and Philosophy of Education.Peter Gilroy - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):202-218.
    This article was first published in 1982 in Educational Analysis (4, 75–91) and republished in 1998 (Hirst, P. H., & White, P. (Eds.), Philosophy of education: Major themes in the analytic tradition, Vol. 1, Philosophy and education, Part 1, pp. 61–78. London: Routledge). I was then a lecturer in philosophy of education at Sheffield University teaching the subject to Master’s students on both full- and part-time programmes. My first degree was in philosophy, read under D. W. Hamlyn and David Cooper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Autonomy in R. S. Peters' Educational Theory.Stefaan E. Cuypers - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):189-207.
    Autonomy is, among other things, an actual psychological condition, a capacity that can be developed, and an educational ideal. This paper contextualises, analyses, criticises and extends the theory of Richard S. Peters on these three aspects of autonomy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Work, the aims of life and the aims of education: A reply to Clarke and Mearman.Christopher Winch - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):633–638.
    The main points made by Clarke and Mearman about Winch's article ‘The Economic Aims of Education’ are taken up and discussed. My argument is that work is not necessarily a disutility, although paid employment can be when it is undertaken in conditions that are not fulfilling. Life aims are not the same as educational aims, although educational aims (as opposed to specific curricular aims) are life aims, and can include vocational preparation, a position endorsed in the later writings of R. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The quest for the good life in Rousseau's Emile: an assessment.Yossi Yonah - 1993 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 12 (2):229-243.
    Rousseau's Emile has attracted an avalanche of critical responses. His theme of negative education, or as he defines it, “well-regulated freedom”, has been denounced as outright manipulation in disguise, which instead of respecting the child's autonomy and dignity, places him at the whim of the teacher's machinations and stratagems. His recommendation that the child's imagination be curtailed (that he may not acquire desires which cannot be satisfied) is widely held to militate against one of the most cherished goals of education: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On understanding educational theory.David Carr - 1985 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 17 (2):19–28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • R. S. Peters and J. H. Newman on the Aims of Education.Jānis Ozoliņš - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):153-170.
    R. S. Peters never explicitly talks about wisdom as being an aim of education. He does, however, in numerous places, emphasize that education is of the whole person and that, whatever else it might be about, it involves the development of knowledge and understanding. Being educated, he claims, is incompatible with being narrowly specialized. Moreover, he argues, education enables a person to have a different perspective on things, ‘to travel with a different view’ [Peters, R. S. (1967). What is an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Making Room for Children's Autonomy: Maria Montessori's Case for Seeing Children's Incapacity for Autonomy as an External Failing.Patrick R. Frierson - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (3):332-350.
    This article draws on Martha Nussbaum's distinction between basic, internal, and external capacities to better specify possible locations for children's ‘incapacity’ for autonomy. I then examine Maria Montessori's work on what she calls ‘normalization’, which involves a release of children's capacities for autonomy and self-governance made possible by being provided with the right kind of environment. Using Montessori, I argue that, in contrast to many ordinary and philosophical assumptions, children's incapacities for autonomy are best understood as consequences of an absence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Learning difficulties and the concept of a person.Andrew Brennan & Paul Dumbleton - 1989 - British Journal of Educational Studies 37 (2):147-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Rousseau as progressive instrurnentalist.John Darling - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (1):27–39.
    In Emile Rousseau emphasises four pedagogical principles which have become associated with child-centred education. Rousseau's conception of education, however, is utilitarian. This combination of principles and overall conception anticipates one particular strand of policy thinking today: the ‘new vocationalism’. As a postscript, this paper asks why little work in the history of philosophy of education has been done, and identifies the early arguments of R. S. Peters as responsible for this failure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Why the Aims of Education Cannot Be Settled.Atli Harðarson - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 46 (2):223-235.
    The dominant model of curriculum design in the last century assumed that school education could be organized around aims, defined primarily in terms of students' behaviour. The credentials of this model were questioned by, among others, Lawrence Stenhouse, who pointed out that education serves purposes that cannot be stated in terms of behavioural objectives. In this article, I offer support for Stenhouse's conclusion and go beyond it, showing that if education aims at critical understanding of its own value, then it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Transformation and Education: The Voice of the Learner in Peters' Concept of Teaching.Andrea English - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):75-95.
    On several occasions in his work, R. S. Peters identifies a difficulty inherent in teaching that underscores the complexity of this relationship: the teacher has the task of passing on knowledge while at the same time allowing knowledge that is passed on to be criticised and revised by the learner. This inquiry asks: first, how does Peters envisage these two tasks coming together in teaching, and, second, does he go far enough in developing what it means for the teacher to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plato and the love of learning.Geoffrey Hinchliffe - 2006 - Ethics and Education 1 (2):117-131.
    This paper explores the relation between love, learning and knowledge as found in three dialogues of Plato, Symposium, Phaedrus and Republic. It argues that the account of the ascent from carnal desire to the love of beauty, as set out in the Symposium, is best seen in terms of a genealogy of love in which the object of love is transformed into an object of knowledge. The Phaedrus shows us how affection and love between two individuals can help motivate a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • R. S. Peters: The reasonableness of ethics.Felicity Haynes - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):142-152.
    This article will begin by examining the extent to which R. S. Peters merited the charge of analytic philosopher. His background in social psychology allowed him to become more pragmatic and grounded in social conventions and ordinary language than the analytic philosophers associated with empiricism, and his gradual shift from requiring internal consistency to developing a notion of ?reasonableness?, in which reason could be tied to passion, grounded him in an idiosyncratic notion of ethics which included compassion and virtue as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations