Switch to: References

Citations of:

How We Think

Philosophical Review 20 (4):441 (1911)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Critical Pragmatism and the Appropriation of Ethnography by Philosophy of Education.Walter Feinberg - 2014 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 34 (2):149-157.
    In this essay I explore the potential that ethnographic methods hold for philosophy of education as a form of critical pragmatism. An aim of critical pragmatism is to help to analyze the roadblocks to fruitful communication, coordination and liberation. It does so by identifying their sources and opportunities for repair. As I have argued elsewhere :222–240, 2012) an important aim of critical pragmatism is to redirect expert knowledge so it takes seriously local understanding. In this essay I do two things. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three Approaches to Doing Philosophy: a Proposal for Grouping Philosophical Exercises in Classroom Teaching.Natascha Kienstra, Machiel Karskens & Jeroen Imants - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (2):288-318.
    Classroom teaching has two aims: learning philosophy, that is, the great philosophers, and doing philosophy. This article provides an overview of thirty exercises that can be used for doing philosophy, grouped into three approaches. The first approach, doing philosophy as connective truth finding or communicative action, is related to such philosophers as Dewey and Arendt, and is illustrated by the Socratic method. The second, doing philosophy as test-based truth finding, is related to such philosophers as Popper, and is illustrated by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Affirming the consequent.George Bowles - 1996 - Argumentation 10 (4):429-444.
    The thesis of this paper is that an argument's possessing the form of affirming the consequent does not suffice to make its premises at all favorably relevant to its conclusion. In support of this thesis I assume two premises and argue for a third. My two assumptions are these: (1) that an argument's possessing the form of affirming the consequent does not suffice to make its conclusion certain relative to its premises (this is widely, if not universally, acknowledged by writers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pragmatist Resources for Experimental Philosophy: Inquiry in Place of Intuition.Colin Koopman - 2012 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 26 (1):1-24.
    Recent attention given to the upstart movement of experimental philosophy is much deserved. But now that experimental philosophy is beginning to enter a stage of maturity, it is time to consider its relation to other philosophical traditions that have issued similar assaults against ingrained and potentially misguided philosophical habits. Experimental philosophy is widely known for rejecting a philosophical reliance on intuitions as evidence in philosophical argument. In this it shares much with another branch of empiricist philosophy, namely, pragmatism. Taking Kwame (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Intelligence and rationality in evolution and culture.Jay Schulkin - 1987 - World Futures 23 (4):275-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Role of a Facilitator in a Community of Philosophical Inquiry.David Kennedy - 2004 - Metaphilosophy 35 (5):744-765.
    Community of philosophical inquiry (CPI) is a way of practicing philosophy in a group that is characterized by conversation; that creates its discussion agenda from questions posed by the conversants as a response to some stimulus (whether text or some other media); and that includes discussion of specific philosophers or philosophical traditions, if at all, only in order to develop its own ideas about the concepts under discussion. The epistemological conviction of community of philosophical inquiry is that communal dialogue, facilitated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Human Rationality Challenges Universal Logic.Brian R. Gaines - 2010 - Logica Universalis 4 (2):163-205.
    Tarski’s conceptual analysis of the notion of logical consequence is one of the pinnacles of the process of defining the metamathematical foundations of mathematics in the tradition of his predecessors Euclid, Frege, Russell and Hilbert, and his contemporaries Carnap, Gödel, Gentzen and Turing. However, he also notes that in defining the concept of consequence “efforts were made to adhere to the common usage of the language of every day life.” This paper addresses the issue of what relationship Tarski’s analysis, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Researching to improve theory, policy and practice. An essay review of Viviane Robinson, Problem‐based Methodology: Research for the Improvement of Practice, Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1993.J. C. Walker - 1996 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 28 (2):55-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialogical and Critical Nature of Philosophical Counselling.Blanka Šulavíková - 2015 - Human Affairs 25 (4):471-485.
    The article looks at critical thinking in philosophical counselling and the concepts upon which it is based. In conceptions that place critical thinking as the basis of philosophical counselling, an important role is played by the Socratic approach to philosophising. The Socratic method in thinking allocates a fundamental role to conversation, and thus to intersubjectivity, and is therefore an alternative to individual ways of thinking. Conversation as philosophical reflection corresponds to the Socratic intersubjective understanding of truth. The author adopts the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding Problem‐Based Learning1.Don Margetson - 1993 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 25 (1):40-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The role of intuition in thinking and learning: Deleuze and the pragmatic legacy.Inna Semetsky - 2004 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 36 (4):433–454.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Platonic dialogue, maieutic method and critical thinking.Fiona Leigh - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (3):309–323.
    In this paper I offer a reading of one of Plato's later works, the Sophist, that reveals it to be informed by principles comparable on the face of it with those that have emerged recently in the field of critical thinking. As a development of the famous Socratic method of his teacher, I argue, Plato deployed his own pedagogical method, a ‘mid‐wifely’ or ‘maieutic’ method, in the Sophist. In contrast to the Socratic method, the sole aim of this method is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Old and new conceptions of discovery in education.D. J. Corson - 1990 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 22 (2):26–49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Teaching thinking, and the sanctity of content.Michael Bonnett - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 29 (3):295–309.
    There are renewed claims that thinking, or important aspects of it, should be conceived in terms of certain general powers, skills or competencies which should be taught as such. Some possibilities for confusion within this view are identified and it is argued that its undoubted attractions must be weighed against certain severe dangers, particularly with regard to how it may predispose us to conceive of content and its role in thinking. Some implications for teaching of a view of thinking that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A view from somewhere: Explaining the paradigms of educational research.Hanan A. Alexander - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (2):205–221.
    In this paper I ask how educational researchers can believe the subjective perceptions of qualitative participant-observers given the concern for objectivity and generalisability of experimental research in the behavioural and social sciences. I critique the most common answer to this question within the educational research community, which posits the existence of two (or more) equally legitimate epistemological paradigms—positivism and constructivism—and offer an alternative that places a priority in educational research on understanding the purposes and meanings humans attribute to educational practices. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Agent-environment interaction perspectives to embodied skilled action: driving beyond information-processing models.Pankaj Singh & A. V. Ravishankar Sarma - forthcoming - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences:1-19.
    The idea of representation is central to many theories for embodied skillful action. Representation-centric cognition has been questioned in light of the prominence of E-cognition in the past two decades, including ecological psychology, sensorimotor theory, dynamical systems, and 4E cognition. The paper expands on the critique by offering alternate explanations for the information processing model of skill learning and embodied action. Mental representation plays a fundamental role in information processing explanations of embodied skillful action. The skilled activity is considered discretely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inquiry and trust: An epistemic balancing act.Heather Rabenberg - 2024 - Philosophical Studies 181 (2-3):583-601.
    It might initially appear impossible to inquire into whether p while trusting someone that p. At the very least, it might appear that doing so would be irrational. In this paper, I shall argue that things are not as they appear. Not only is it possible for a person to inquire into whether p while trusting someone that p, it is very often rational. Indeed, combining inquiry and trust in this way is an epistemic balancing act central to a well-lived (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Laughter as Natural Piety: John Dewey, Humor, and the Religious.Jonathan Weidenbaum - 2023 - The Philosophy of Humor Yearbook 4 (1):27-51.
    One topic frequently explored in the philosophy of humor is the relationship of comedy and laughter with other facets of human existence—including theological insight and religious experience. The aim of this essay is to employ the mature thought of John Dewey not only to illuminate the nature of humor, but also to discern the deep source and connection between the spiritually exalting and the funny from a naturalistic perspective. While a number of passages on comedy and humor from Dewey’s later (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From critical thinking to criticality and back again.Henri Pettersson - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 57 (2):478-494.
    This paper assesses the prospects of combining the distinctive strengths of the two major educational research programs of critical thinking and critical pedagogy—or, described more accurately, overcoming their shared limitations—in a new and superior educational objective called criticality. Several recent proposals explore the possibilities of engaging in bridge-building between these camps. The plan is that the distinctive strengths of these paradigms—the logical and epistemological precision of critical thinking together with the socio-political consciousness of critical pedagogy—could complement each other, while the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Feeling and thinking on social media: emotions, affective scaffolding, and critical thinking.Steffen Steinert, Lavinia Marin & Sabine Roeser - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):1-28.
    It is often suggested that social media is a hostile environment for critical thinking and that a major source for epistemic problems concerning social media is that it facilitates emotions. We argue that emotions per se are not the source of the epistemic problems concerning social media. We propose that instead of focusing on emotions, we should focus on the affective scaffolding of social media. We will show that some affective scaffolds enable desirable epistemic practices, while others obstruct beneficial epistemic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interpretive description in applied mixed methods research: Exploring issues of fit, purpose, process, context, and design.Sara Dolan, Lorelli Nowell & Nancy J. Moules - 2023 - Nursing Inquiry 30 (3):e12542.
    As mixed methods research approaches become increasingly more common, it is imperative they are conducted in a thoughtful and rigorous manner to yield useful results. While researchers have begun to explore the use of various qualitative research methodologies in mixed methods research, there is a gap in literature discussing the philosophical congruence of using interpretive description in mixed method studies, and how to ensure rigor while integrating interpretive description results. Our purpose in writing this article is to discuss the issues (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Expert Text Analysis in the Inclusion of History and Philosophy of Science in Higher Education.Vitaly Pronskikh & Galina V. Sorina - 2022 - Science & Education 31 (4):961-975.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Drawing Inferences: Thinking with 6B.Sabine Ammon - 2019 - Philosophy and Technology 32 (4):591-612.
    This article discusses the epistemology of design as a process, arguing specifically that sketching and drawing are essential modes of thinking and reasoning. It demonstrates that the commonly accepted notion of a spontaneous and intuitive vision in the mind’s eye—encapsulated in the cliché of the napkin sketch—obscures the exploratory inferences that are made while scribbling with a pencil on a sheet of paper. The draughtsperson, along with their work tools, modes of notation, specific techniques, and epistemic strategies as well as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dewey as Virtue Epistemologist: Open‐Mindedness and the Training of Thought in Democracy and Education.Ben Kotzee - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 52 (2):359-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Let Us Investigate! Dynamic Conjecture-Making as the Formal Logic of Abduction.Minghui Ma & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (6):913-945.
    We present a dynamic approach to Peirce’s original construal of abductive logic as a logic of conjecture making, and provide a new decidable, contraction-free and cut-free proof system for the dynamic logic of abductive inferences with neighborhood semantics. Our formulation of the dynamic logic of abduction follows the philosophical and scientific track that led Peirce to his late, post-1903 characterization of abductive conclusions as investigands, namely invitations to investigate propositions conjectured at the level of pre-beliefs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Rousseau et l’éducation : apports et tensions.Stéphane Martineau & Alexandre Buysse - 2016 - Revue Phronesis 5 (2):14-22.
    Rousseau’s thoughts on education are being presented and then put in tension with todays educational conceptions. We aim at highlighting in how far Rousseau’s work can still contribute to conceive teaching and learning, but also how it is in tension with some contemporary educational tenets. We conclude by emphasising the need to reflect all teaching and learning taking into account the objective to allow the development of a human being bestowed with a unique potential, that of being able to become (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Essential Uncertainty of Thinking: Education and Subject in John Dewey.Vasco D'agnese - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 51 (1):73-88.
    In this paper, I analyse the Deweyan account of thinking and subject and discuss the educational consequences that follow from such an account. I argue that despite the grouping of thinking and reflective thought that has largely appeared in the interpretation of Deweyan work, Dewey discloses an inescapable uncertainty at the core of human thinking. This move is even more challenging given Dewey's firm faith in the power of intelligent action, and in education as the means by which human beings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Community of Philosophical Inquiry as a Discursive Structure, and its Role in School Curriculum Design.Nadia Kennedy & David Kennedy - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 45 (2):265-283.
    This article traces the development of the theory and practice of what is known as ‘community of inquiry’ as an ideal of classroom praxis. The concept has ancient and uncertain origins, but was seized upon as a form of pedagogy by the originators of the Philosophy for Children program in the 1970s. Its location at the intersection of the discourses of argumentation theory, communications theory, semiotics, systems theory, dialogue theory, learning theory and group psychodynamics makes of it a rich site (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Do Programmes Delineating Critical Thinking as a Learning Outcome Facilitate its Teaching? International Baccalaureate Diploma Programme and Lebanese Baccalaureate Programme.Yara Yasser Hilal - 2018 - Topoi 37 (1):201-217.
    Critical thinking continues to be viewed as a prerequisite skill for lifelong learning. It is not surprising therefore, that academic programmes delineate CT as a goal and a learning outcome. However, there are concerns regarding the extent to which the aims and objectives of the programmes are aligned with pedagogies for CT. Both the International Baccalaureate Diploma Programme and the Lebanese Baccalaureate Programme clearly delineate CT as a goal and a learning outcome. The study examines the facilitation of teaching CT (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Charles Bingham, Barry Kanpol, Shawn Taylor, Ann E. Fordon, Stanley D. Ivie, Douglas W. Doyle, Robert Lawy, John C. Scott, Terry A. Osborn, Barbara J. Thayer-Bacon, William B. Stanley, Lynn W. Stanley & Donald Vandenberg - 2000 - Educational Studies 31 (4):427-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Epistemology of Education.Lani Watson - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (3):146-159.
    The landscape of contemporary epistemology has significantly diversified in the past 30 years, shaped in large part by two complementary movements: virtue and social epistemology. This diversification provides an apt theoretical context for the epistemology of education. No longer concerned exclusively with the formal analysis of knowledge, epistemologists have turned their attention towards individuals as knowers, and the social contexts in which epistemic goods such as knowledge and understanding are acquired and exchanged. As such, the concerns of epistemology have once (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • ‘It was the Best of Times, it was the Worst of Times …’: Philosophy of Education in the Contemporary World.Peter Roberts - 2014 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 34 (6):623-634.
    This article considers the state of philosophy of education in our current age and assesses prospects for the future of the field. I argue that as philosophers of education, we live in both the best of times and the worst of times. Developments in one key organisation, the Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia, are examined in relation to broader international trends. Informed by the work of Pierre Hadot, I also reflect on what it might mean to talk of philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Self-Assessment of Professional Growth Through Reflective Portfolios.Jodi Nickel - 2013 - Revue Phronesis 2 (1):67-79.
    Cette étude vise à trouver comment les futurs enseignants développent la capacité de réflexion par l’auto-évaluation sur leurs portfolios. Bien que le but était d’aider les enseignants en première année de formation à évaluer leurs progrès vers la réalisation des compétences provinciales, plusieurs d’entre eux ont attiré l’attention des chercheurs sur les liens entre leurs artéfacts universitaires et leurs profils personnels. Ce développement a conduit les chercheurs à affiner la finalité du portfolio pour soutenir l’émergence d’une identité professionnelle et au (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deleuze's new image of thought, or Dewey revisited.Inna Semetsky - 2003 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (1):17–29.
    Richard Rorty, in his ‘Consequences of Pragmatism’ (1982), acknowledging the pragmatic direction taken by both modern and postmodern philosophy, declared that ‘James and Dewey were not only waiting at the end of the dialectical road which analytic philosophy traveled, but are waiting at the end of the road which, for example, Foucault and Deleuze are currently traveling’ (Rorty, 1982, p. xviii). This paper does not aim to establish who traveled the farthest along the road posited by Rorty. Instead, its purpose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Action Guidance and Educating for Intellectual Virtue: A Response to Kotzee, Carter, and Siegel.Matthew McKeon & Matthew Ferkany - 2023 - Episteme:1-21.
    In their “Educating for Intellectual Virtue: A Critique from Action Guidance” Kotzee, Carter and Siegel (2019) argue against what they call the intellectual virtues (IV) approach to the primary epistemic aim of education and in favor of what they call the critical thinking (CT) approach. The IV approach says that educating for intellectual virtue is the primary epistemic aim of education. The CT approach says that it is educating for critical thinking. They argue that the exemplarist/role-modeling pedagogy of the IV (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Tyranny of ‘Teaching and Learning’.Alex Buckley - 2021 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 40 (4):415-427.
    The phrase ‘teaching and learning’ has essentially replaced the word ‘teaching’ in educational discourse. The linguistic shift occurred as part of a wider movement in the 1980s and 1990s to give greater attention to learning in the educational process, and the phrase served a sloganistic function. With the learning paradigm now largely uncontroversial, the phrase—like other ex-slogans—may now be carrying implications more tied to its literal meaning. This paper suggests that the constant reference to learning in the context of teaching (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shadow education in Singapore: A Deweyan perspective.Peter Teo & Dorothy Koh - 2019 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 52 (8):869-879.
    This study focuses on the phenomenon of private supplementary tutoring, otherwise known as ‘shadow education’, which has proliferated around the world. By casting the spotlight on one parti...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Com-Posting Experimental Futures: Pragmatists Making (Odd)Kin with New Materialists.Barbara S. Stengel - 2018 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 38 (1):7-29.
    Here I craft a case for recognizing the roots and patterns that ground the possibility of contemporary com-posting—as outlined in Donna Haraway’s Staying with the Trouble—by New Materialists and critical pragmatists, especially those who are affected by the social injustices and ill-advised practices of today’s formal education. I explore both Spinozan Ethics and American pragmatism in order to fashion a pattern that affects educational thought and action. That pattern of affect/affecting is one Haraway calls “attunement”, a state of co-relation that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Settling no Conflict in the Public Place: Truth in education, and in Rancièrean scholarship.Charles Bingham - 2010 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 42 (5-6):649-665.
    This essay offers an educational understanding of truth deriving from the work of Jacques Rancière. Unlike other educational accounts—the traditional, progressive, and critical accounts—of truth that take education as a way of approaching pre‐existing truths (or lack of pre‐existing truths), this essay establishes an account of truth that is intrinsic to education. It uses Rancière's language theory to do so, showing that Rancière's own perspective on truth is in fact opposed to the one so often promoted in and through education. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Interpreting children's ideas: Creative thought or factual belief? A new look at Piaget's theory of childhood artificialism as related to religious education.Elizabeth Ashton - 1993 - British Journal of Educational Studies 41 (2):164-173.
    . Interpreting children 's ideas: Creative thought or factual belief? A new look at Piaget's theory of childhood artificialism as related to religious education. British Journal of Educational Studies: Vol. 41, No. 2, pp. 164-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is monitoring one’s actions causally relevant to choking under pressure?Barbara Gail Montero - 2015 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14 (2):379-395.
    I have a painfully vivid memory of performing the Venezuelan choreographer Vincente Nebrada’s ballet Pentimento.After graduating from high school at age 15 and before entering college, I spent a number of years working as a professional ballet dancer with North Carolina Dance Theatre , among other companies. I was a new member of North Carolina Dance Theatre, and although the company had presented the piece on a number of occasions, this was the first time the director was watching from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The pre-theoreticality of moral intuitions.Christopher B. Kulp - 2014 - Synthese 191 (15):3759-3778.
    Moral intuitionism, once an apparently moribund metaethical position, has seen a resurgence of interest of late. Robert Audi, a leading moral intuitionist, has argued that in order for a moral belief to qualify as intuitional, it must fulfill four criteria: it must be non-inferential, firmly held, comprehended, and pre-theoretical. This paper centers on the fourth and seemingly most problematic criterion: pre-theoreticality. The paper begins by stipulating the defensibility of the moral cognitivism upon which moral intuitionism turns. Next, the paper develops (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Anscombe's 'Teachers'.Jeremy Wanderer - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 47 (2):204-221.
    This article is an investigation into G. E. M. Anscombe's suggestion that there can be cases where belief takes a personal object, through an examination of the role that the activity of teaching plays in Anscombe's discussion. By contrasting various kinds of ‘teachers’ that feature in her discussion, it is argued that the best way of understanding the idea of believing someone personally is to situate the relevant encounter within the social, conversational framework of ‘engaged reasoning’. Key features of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dealing with Diversity: On the Uses of Common Sense in Descartes and Montaigne.Darryl M. De Marzio - 2010 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 29 (3):301-313.
    This essay attempts to retrieve the notion of ‘common sense’ within the writings of Descartes and Montaigne. I suggest that both writers represent distinct traditions in which the notion is employed. Descartes represents a modernist tradition in which common sense is understood to be a cognitive faculty, while Montaigne represents a humanist tradition in which common sense is understood as a political virtue. I also suggest that both writers work with the notion as a way of responding to diversity in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Education(al) Research, Educational Policy-Making and Practice.Charles Clark - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 45 (1):37-57.
    Professor Whitty has endorsed the consensus that research into education is empirical social science, distinguishing ‘educational research’ which seeks directly to influence practice, and ‘education research’ that has substantive value but no necessary practical application.The status of the science here is problematic. The positivist approach is incoherent and so supports neither option. Critical educational science is virtually policy-inert. The interpretive approach is empirically sound but, because of the value component in education, does not support education research either, or account for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Centring the subject in order to educate.R. Scott Webster - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (5):519–530.
    It is important for educators to recognise that the various calls to decentre the subject—or self—should not be interpreted as necessarily requiring the removal of the subject altogether. Through the individualism of the Enlightenment the self was centred. This highly individualistic notion of the sovereign self has now been decentred especially through post‐structuralist literature. It is contended here however, that this tendency to decentre the subject has been taken to an extreme at times, especially by some designers of school frameworks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A myth in language teacher learning: Lesson observation.Min Gu - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    This study explores the learning process of 32 Chinese senior high school English as a foreign language teachers via three demonstration lessons. It was demonstrated via a data analysis of oral reports and interviews that the cognitive activity of “question,” which was considered a significant contributor to collaborative discussion, was seldom involved in the participating teachers’ learning process, and that the absence of this cognitive activity reduced their learning to individual study of the observed practical skills. The study further reveals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Promoting virtual, informal learning now to thrive in a post‐pandemic world.Stephanie Zajac, Jason Randall & Courtney Holladay - 2022 - Business and Society Review 127 (S1):283-298.
    Business and Society Review, Volume 127, Issue S1, Page 283-298, Spring 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Coronavirus Disease 2019: Exploring Media Portrayals of Public Sentiment on Funerals Using Linguistic Dimensions.Sweta Saraff, Tushar Singh & Ramakrishna Biswal - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12:626638.
    Funerals are a reflective practice to bid farewell to the departed soul. Different religions, cultural traditions, rituals, and social beliefs guide how funeral practices take place. Family and friends gather together to support each other in times of grief. However, during the coronavirus pandemic, the way funerals are taking place is affected by the country's rules and region to avoid the spread of infection. The present study explores the media portrayal of public sentiments over funerals. In particular, the present study (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ignorance, misconceptions and critical thinking.Sara Dellantonio & Luigi Pastore - 2020 - Synthese 198 (8):7473-7501.
    In this paper we investigate ignorance in relation to our capacity to justify our beliefs. To achieve this aim we specifically address scientific misconceptions, i.e. beliefs that are considered to be false in light of accepted scientific knowledge. The hypothesis we put forward is that misconceptions are not isolated false beliefs, but rather form part of a system of inferences—an explanation—which does not match current scientific theory. We further argue that, because misconceptions are embedded in a system, they cannot be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark