Switch to: References

Citations of:

Philosophia Naturalis

[author unknown]
Philosophia Naturalis 28:116-116 (1991)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. De Volder’s Cartesian Physics and Experimental Pedagogy.Tammy Nyden - 2013 - In Mihnea Dobre Tammy Nyden (ed.), Cartesian Empiricisms. Dordrecht: Springer.
    In 1675, Burchard de Volder (1643–1709) was the first professor to introduce the demonstration of experiment into a university physics course and built the Leiden Physics Theatre to accommodate this new pedagogy. When he requested the funds from the university to build the facility, he claimed that the performance of experiments would demonstrate the “truth and certainty” of the postulates of theoretical physics. Such a claim is interesting given de Volder’s lifelong commitment to Cartesian scientia. This chapter will examine de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The natural, the secular and the supernatural.Gustavo Caponi - 2019 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 14:27-55.
    In Philosophy of Biology, but also in Philosophy of Mind, in Ethics, in Epistemology, and even in Aesthetics, the term naturalization is usually used in two different ways. It is often used in a meta-philosophical sense to indicate a way for doing philosophy that, in some way, would approximate this reflection to scientific research. But it is also often used in a meta-theoretical sense. In that case, it is used to characterize an explanatory operation proper to science. Sometimes, this scientific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • İbn Haldûn’un Ahl'k Düşüncesi Bakımından Money-Hedonizm.Muhammet Caner Ilgaroğlu - 2019 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 23 (3):1331-1347.
    According to Ibn Khaldūn, man is a social entity deeply influenced by the geo-economics-politics of the environment in which he lives. The effect is seen as so strong that nearly all of these structures in their relationship to human beings are dominated by it. In this system, we see human beings as a creature who is both able to adapt himself to the environment and able to evolve in this harmony. From the perspective of Ibn Khaldūn, man cannot be evaluated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descartes on the Heartbeat: The Leuven Affair.Lucian Petrescu - 2013 - Perspectives on Science 21 (4):397-428.
    There is an interesting historical detour in the dissemination of one of the seventeenth century’s most praised discoveries: the reception of Harvey’s account of the circulation of the blood is closely intertwined, especially in the Low Countries, with Descartes’ account of the origin of the heartbeat. Descartes was one of the first figures to support the circulation of the blood and to give credit to Harvey for it, although he presumably arrived at the same conclusion independently through his own anatomical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Action and Reaction before Newton.John L. Russell - 1976 - British Journal for the History of Science 9 (1):25-38.
    The concepts of action and reaction before Newton have received so little attention from historians that the unwary student might easily get the impression that Newton was the first to concern himself seriously with the problem. In fact, the subject had a long prehistory extending back to Aristotle and it was actively discussed by physicists during the half-century preceding the publication of Principia mathematica in 1687. Although there is no evidence that Newton himself was much influenced by the views of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Louis de La Forge and the 'Non-Transfer Argument' for Occasionalism.Andrea Sangiacomo - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (1):60-80.
    In this paper, I investigate Louis de La Forge's argument against body–body causation. His general strategy exploits the impossibility of bodies communicating their movement by transfer of motion. I call this the ‘non-transfer’ argument . NT allows La Forge both to reinterpret continuous creation in an occasionalistic fashion and to support his non-occasionalistic view concerning mind–body union. First, I present how NT emerges in Descartes’ own texts. Second, I show how La Forge recasts it to draw an occasionalistic account of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Review essay: The importance of the history of science for philosophy in general. [REVIEW]Gary Hatfield - 1996 - Synthese 106 (1):113 - 138.
    Essay review of Daniel Garber, 1992, Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, xiv + 389 pp., and Michael Friedman,: 1992, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., and London, xvii + 357 pp. These two books display the historical connection between science and philosophy in the writings of Descartes and Kant. They show the place of science in, or the scientific context of, these authors' central metaphysical doctrines, pertaining to substance and its properties, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Descartes and the Dutch: Botanical Experimentation in the Early Modern Period.Fabrizio Baldassarri - 2020 - Perspectives on Science 28 (6):657-683.
    Early modern study of plants blossomed in a network of observation, exchanges, collaborations, and epistolary discussions. Following Baconian methodology, Dutch scholars combined the labor of listing and describing plants with botanical experimentation. This empirical approach was a suitable context for Descartes, who exchanged information and performed observations on plants in collaboration with Dutch experimenters. In this article, I focus on (1) the reception of a few botanical experiments of Bacon’s Sylva Sylvarum in Huygens and Reneri, with whom Descartes was in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Glass-Drops: a case Study of the Interplay between Experimentation and Explanation in Seventeenth-Century Natural Philosophy.Mihnea Dobre - 2013 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 2 (1):105-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kepler's Second Law in England.Victor E. Thoren - 1974 - British Journal for the History of Science 7 (3):243-256.
    In two recent articles by Russell and Whiteside, the reception of those particular conclusions of Kepler that have come to be called his laws of planetary motion has been subjected to the first research beyond the pioneering efforts of Delambre at the beginning of the nineteenth century. Independently conceived, and directed towards quite different ends, these two investigations overlapped in only one substantial area—their survey of citations of Kepler's second law by English astronomers between 1650 and 1670. Not surprisingly, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The mechanical life of plants: Descartes on botany.Fabrizio Baldassarri - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Science 52 (1):41-63.
    In this article, I argue that the French philosopher René Descartes was far more involved in the study of plants than has been generally recognized. We know that he did not include a botanical section in his natural philosophy, and sometimes he differentiated between plants and living bodies. His position was, moreover, characterized by a methodological rejection of the catalogues of plants. However, this paper reveals a significant trend in Descartes's naturalistic pursuits, starting from the end of 1637, whereby he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Natural Philosophy in Renaissance Italy: the University of Bologna and the Beginnings of Specialization.David A. Lines - 2001 - Early Science and Medicine 6 (4):267-320.
    In the Italian universities, there was traditionally a strong alliance between natural philosophy and medicine, which however was all to the advantage of the latter; its teachers were better regarded and better paid than others in the faculty of Arts and Medicine, and this led to career paths that sought out the teaching of medicine as soon as possible. This article examines a reversal of this trend observable in sixteenth-century Bologna and some other Italian universities , leading to careers concentrating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cartesian Certainty and the Infinity of the Will.Joseph K. Cosgrove - 2004 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 21 (4):377 - 396.
    This paper interprets Descartes' conception of "certainty" as most fundamentally a function of the human will, controlling the cognitive encounter with the world.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meteors and mixtures. Problems of hylomorphic composition.Lucian Petrescu - 2014 - Dissertation, Ghent University
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant and modern physics--The synthetic a priori and the distinction between modal function and entity.D. F. M. Strauss - 2000 - South African Journal of Philosophy 19 (1):26-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation