Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning: Induction and analogy in mathematics

Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press (1954)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Critical Studies / Book Reviews.Bart Kerkhove - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):69-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heuristics and Inferential Microstructures: The Path to Quaternions.Emiliano Ippoliti - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (3):411-425.
    I investigate the construction of the mathematical concept of quaternion from a methodological and heuristic viewpoint to examine what we can learn from it for the study of the advancement of mathematical knowledge. I will look, in particular, at the inferential microstructures that shape this construction, that is, the study of both the very first, ampliative inferential steps, and their tentative outcomes—i.e. small ‘structures’ such as provisional entities and relations. I discuss how this paradigmatic case study supports the recent approaches (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Beauty Is Not Simplicity: An Analysis of Mathematicians' Proof Appraisals.Matthew Inglis & Andrew Aberdein - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1):87-109.
    What do mathematicians mean when they use terms such as ‘deep’, ‘elegant’, and ‘beautiful’? By applying empirical methods developed by social psychologists, we demonstrate that mathematicians' appraisals of proofs vary on four dimensions: aesthetics, intricacy, utility, and precision. We pay particular attention to mathematical beauty and show that, contrary to the classical view, beauty and simplicity are almost entirely unrelated in mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Mathematics and Symbolic Logics: Some Notes on an Uneasy Relationship.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):159-167.
    Symbolic logics tend to be too mathematical for the philosophers and too philosophical for the mathematicians; and their history is too historical for most mathematicians, philosophers and logicians. This paper reflects upon these professional demarcations as they have developed during the century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Probing the “Achilles' heel” of rational analysis.Keith J. Holyoak - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):498-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analogical Mapping by Constraint Satisfaction.Keith J. Holyoak & Paul Thagard - 1989 - Cognitive Science 13 (3):295-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Bayes in the context of suboptimality.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):497-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Optimality and psychological explanation.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):496-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does the environment have the same structure as Bayes' theorem?Gerd Gigerenzer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):495-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beyond Helmholtz, or why not include inner determinants from the beginning?Hans-Georg Geissler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):494-495.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A model of argumentation and its application to legal reasoning.Kathleen Freeman & Arthur M. Farley - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 4 (3-4):163-197.
    We present a computational model of dialectical argumentation that could serve as a basis for legal reasoning. The legal domain is an instance of a domain in which knowledge is incomplete, uncertain, and inconsistent. Argumentation is well suited for reasoning in such weak theory domains. We model argument both as information structure, i.e., argument units connecting claims with supporting data, and as dialectical process, i.e., an alternating series of moves by opposing sides. Our model includes burden of proof as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Teaching and Learning Science in Hungary, 1867–1945: Schools, Personalities, Influences.Tibor Frank - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (3):355-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-deductive logic in mathematics.James Franklin - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1):1-18.
    Mathematicians often speak of conjectures as being confirmed by evidence that falls short of proof. For their own conjectures, evidence justifies further work in looking for a proof. Those conjectures of mathematics that have long resisted proof, such as Fermat's Last Theorem and the Riemann Hypothesis, have had to be considered in terms of the evidence for and against them. It is argued here that it is not adequate to describe the relation of evidence to hypothesis as `subjective', `heuristic' or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • El matemático como un profesional en los recorridos de estudio e investigación.C. Fonseca, J. M. Casas & M. A. Insua - 2011 - Arbor 187 (Extra_3):279-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rational analysis and illogical inference.Edmund Fantino & Stephanie Stolarz-Fantino - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):494-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptive cognition: The question is how.Jonathan St B. T. Evans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):493-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lakatos between Marxism and the Hungarian heuristic tradition.Val Dusek - 2015 - Studies in East European Thought 67 (1-2):61-73.
    Imre Lakatos gained fame in the English-speaking world as a follower and critic of philosopher of science Karl Popper. However, Lakatos’ background involved other philosophical and scientific sources from his native Hungary. Lakatos surreptitiously used Hegelian Marxism in his works on philosophy of science and mathematics, disguising it with the rhetoric of the Popper school. He also less surreptitiously incorporated, particularly in his treatment of mathematics, work of the strong tradition of heuristics in twentieth century Hungary. Both his Marxism and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards a theory of mathematical argument.Ian J. Dove - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (1-2):136-152.
    In this paper, I assume, perhaps controversially, that translation into a language of formal logic is not the method by which mathematicians assess mathematical reasoning. Instead, I argue that the actual practice of analyzing, evaluating and critiquing mathematical reasoning resembles, and perhaps equates with, the practice of informal logic or argumentation theory. It doesn’t matter whether the reasoning is a full-fledged mathematical proof or merely some non-deductive mathematical justification: in either case, the methodology of assessment overlaps to a large extent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Argument of Mathematics.Andrew Aberdein & Ian J. Dove (eds.) - 2013 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Written by experts in the field, this volume presents a comprehensive investigation into the relationship between argumentation theory and the philosophy of mathematical practice. Argumentation theory studies reasoning and argument, and especially those aspects not addressed, or not addressed well, by formal deduction. The philosophy of mathematical practice diverges from mainstream philosophy of mathematics in the emphasis it places on what the majority of working mathematicians actually do, rather than on mathematical foundations. -/- The book begins by first challenging the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematical practice: A primer for mathematics educators.Yacin Hamami & Rebecca Morris - 2020 - ZDM Mathematics Education 52:1113–1126.
    In recent years, philosophical work directly concerned with the practice of mathematics has intensified, giving rise to a movement known as the philosophy of mathematical practice . In this paper we offer a survey of this movement aimed at mathematics educators. We first describe the core questions philosophers of mathematical practice investigate as well as the philosophical methods they use to tackle them. We then provide a selective overview of work in the philosophy of mathematical practice covering topics including the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotelian realism.James Franklin - 2009 - In A. Irvine (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics (Handbook of the Philosophy of Science series). North-Holland Elsevier.
    Aristotelian, or non-Platonist, realism holds that mathematics is a science of the real world, just as much as biology or sociology are. Where biology studies living things and sociology studies human social relations, mathematics studies the quantitative or structural aspects of things, such as ratios, or patterns, or complexity, or numerosity, or symmetry. Let us start with an example, as Aristotelians always prefer, an example that introduces the essential themes of the Aristotelian view of mathematics. A typical mathematical truth is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • What Philosophy of Mathematical Practice Can Teach Argumentation Theory About Diagrams and Pictures.Brendan Larvor - 2013 - In Andrew Aberdein & Ian J. Dove (eds.), The Argument of Mathematics. Springer. pp. 239--253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Non-deductive Logic in Mathematics: The Probability of Conjectures.James Franklin - 2013 - In Andrew Aberdein & Ian J. Dove (eds.), The Argument of Mathematics. Springer. pp. 11--29.
    Mathematicians often speak of conjectures, yet unproved, as probable or well-confirmed by evidence. The Riemann Hypothesis, for example, is widely believed to be almost certainly true. There seems no initial reason to distinguish such probability from the same notion in empirical science. Yet it is hard to see how there could be probabilistic relations between the necessary truths of pure mathematics. The existence of such logical relations, short of certainty, is defended using the theory of logical probability (or objective Bayesianism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Argumentation and learning.Baruch B. Schwarz - 2009 - In Nathalie Muller Mirza & Anne Nelly Perret-Clermont (eds.), Argumentation and Education. Springer. pp. 91--126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mathematical Narratives.James Robert Brown - 2014 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 10 (2):59-73.
    Philosophers and mathematicians have different ideas about the difference between pure and applied mathematics. This should not surprise us, since they have different aims and interests. For mathematicians, pure mathematics is the interesting stuff, even if it has lots of physics involved. This has the consequence that picturesque examples play a role in motivating and justifying mathematical results. Philosophers might find this upsetting, but we find a parallel to mathematician’s attitudes in ethics, which, I argue, is a much better model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical Thinking Undefended on The Level of The Semester for Professional Mathematics Teacher Candidates. Toheri & Widodo Winarso - 2017 - Munich University Library.
    Mathematical thinking skills are very important in mathematics, both to learn math or as learning goals. Thinking skills can be seen from the description given answers in solving mathematical problems faced. Mathematical thinking skills can be seen from the types, levels, and process. Proportionally questions given to students at universities in Indonesia (semester I, III, V, and VII). These questions are a matter of description that belong to the higher-level thinking. Students choose 5 of 8 given problem. Qualitatively, the answers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Empirically Grounded Philosophical Theorizing.O. Bueno & S. A. Shalkowski - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Analogy and creativity in the works of Johannes Kepler.Dedre Gentner, Sarah Brem, Ron Ferguson, Philip Wolff, Arthur B. Markman & Ken Forbus - 1997 - In T. B. Ward, S. M. Smith & J. Viad (eds.), Creative Thought: An Investigation of Conceptual Structures and Processes. American Psychological Association.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Argument and explanation in mathematics.Michel Dufour - 2013 - In Dima Mohammed and Marcin Lewiński (ed.), Virtues of Argumentation. Proceedings of the 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22-26 May 2013. pp. pp. 1-14..
    Are there arguments in mathematics? Are there explanations in mathematics? Are there any connections between argument, proof and explanation? Highly controversial answers and arguments are reviewed. The main point is that in the case of a mathematical proof, the pragmatic criterion used to make a distinction between argument and explanation is likely to be insufficient for you may grant the conclusion of a proof but keep on thinking that the proof is not explanatory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The dialectical tier of mathematical proof.Andrew Aberdein - 2011 - In Frank Zenker (ed.), Argumentation: Cognition & Community. Proceedings of the 9th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18--21, 2011. OSSA.
    Ralph Johnson argues that mathematical proofs lack a dialectical tier, and thereby do not qualify as arguments. This paper argues that, despite this disavowal, Johnson’s account provides a compelling model of mathematical proof. The illative core of mathematical arguments is held to strict standards of rigour. However, compliance with these standards is itself a matter of argument, and susceptible to challenge. Hence much actual mathematical practice takes place in the dialectical tier.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations