Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Correspondence rules.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (3):280-290.
    The traditional role which correspondence rules, coordinating definitions, or semantical rules, have in a logical analysis of a scientific theory is questioned by providing an alternative analysis. The alternative account suggests that scientific theories are "meaningful" prior to the establishment of correspondence rules, and that correspondence rules are introduced to permit explanation and testing in the "observational" sector. The role of models is briefly assessed in connection with this prior or "antecedent theoretical meaning," and a causal sequence analysis of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • A critique of Popper's views on scientific method.Nicholas Maxwell - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (2):131-152.
    This paper considers objections to Popper's views on scientific method. It is argued that criticism of Popper's views, developed by Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Lakatos, are not too damaging, although they do require that Popper's views be modified somewhat. It is argued that a much more serious criticism is that Popper has failed to provide us with any reason for holding that the methodological rules he advocates give us a better hope of realizing the aims of science than any other set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • El falsacionismo revisado.Luis Felipe Bartolo Alegre - 2021 - Analítica 11 (11):85-102.
    In this paper I formalise the falsificationist proposal omitting Popper’s requirement of consistency. This omission results in (i) trivial theories being falsifiable in an inappropriate sense of the term, but also in (ii) some inconsistent non-trivial theories being so in an appropriate one. This justifies a slight alteration of the definition of falsifiability that excludes (i) but allows (ii). Instead of requiring that a falsifiable theory be consistent, my proposal only requires that the intersection of its classes of potential corroborators (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Externalist’s Guide to Fishing for Compliments.Bernhard Salow - 2018 - Mind 127 (507):691-728.
    Suppose you’d like to believe that p, whether or not it’s true. What can you do to help? A natural initial thought is that you could engage in Intentionally Biased Inquiry : you could look into whether p, but do so in a way that you expect to predominantly yield evidence in favour of p. This paper hopes to do two things. The first is to argue that this initial thought is mistaken: intentionally biased inquiry is impossible. The second is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Automated discovery systems, part 1: Historical origins, main research programs, and methodological foundations.Piotr Giza - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 17 (1):e12800.
    Philosophy Compass, Volume 17, Issue 1, January 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Should we return to the laboratory to find out about learning?J. M. E. Moravcsik - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):529-529.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Methods and theories in the experimental analysis of behavior.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):511-523.
    We owe most scientific knowledge to methods of inquiry that are never formally analyzed. The analysis of behavior does not call for hypothetico-deductive methods. Statistics, taught in lieu of scientific method, is incompatible with major features of much laboratory research. Squeezing significance out of ambiguous data discourages the more promising step of scrapping the experiment and starting again. As a consequence, psychologists have taken flight from the laboratory. They have fled to Real People and the human interest of “real life,” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Real people, ordinary language, and natural measurement.Samuel M. Deitz - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):524-525.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior theory: A contradiction in terms?R. Duncan Luce - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):525-526.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper’s Critique of the Instrumentalist Account of Theories and Theoretical Terms.Paul Tibbetts - 1972 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):57-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Amplifying personal probability theory: Comments on L. J. Savage's "difficulties in the theory of personal probability".Abner Shimony - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (4):326-332.
    Professor Savage has been candid and generous in stating his interest in philosophy, and the philosophers who have heard him are surely grateful for this. His attitude is very far from that of some competent scientists and mathematicans who purport to clear up the questions which philosophers raise concerning their disciplines by means of a battery of technical results of varying relevance—a procedure which can often be appropriately described as “an abominable snow-job.” However, Professor Savage's generosity places a responsibility on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The role of the statistician in psychology.F. H. C. Marriott - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):527-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Ifs and Newcombs.Arthur E. Falk - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):449-481.
    ‘Ifs’ come washed or unwashed. The washed ifs are embedded in precise theories: the constantly strict implication of deductive inference, the variably strict implication of ‘nearness’ conditionals, and statements of conditional probability. By a nearness conditional I mean the common part of Stalnaker's and D. Lewis's theory of counterfactual conditionals, which depends on a notion that possible worlds are more or less near to each other, as a measure of their over-all similarity to each other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Automated Discovery Systems, part 2: New developments, current issues, and philosophical lessons in machine learning and data science.Piotr Giza - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 17 (1):e12802.
    Philosophy Compass, Volume 17, Issue 1, January 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Current questions for the science of behavior.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):535-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Ifs and Newcombs.Arthur E. Falk - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):449 - 481.
    ‘Ifs’ come washed or unwashed. The washed ifs are embedded in precise theories: the constantly strict implication of deductive inference, the variably strict implication of ‘nearness’ conditionals, and statements of conditional probability. By a nearness conditional I mean the common part of Stalnaker's and D. Lewis's theory of counterfactual conditionals, which depends on a notion that possible worlds are more or less near to each other, as a measure of their over-all similarity to each other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Karl Popper and Lamarckism.Elena Aronova - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (1):37-51.
    The article discusses Karl Popper’s account of Lamarckism. In this article I use Popper’s published and unpublished statements regarding Lamarckism as well as his correspondence with the Australian immunologist Edward Steele and other biologists to examine why Popper was interested in Lamarckism, how his account of Lamarckism can be understood in the context of his philosophy, and what, if any, new context Popper provided for the discussion of this abandoned doctrine. I begin by discussing Popper’s frame of reference regarding Lamarckism, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Lessons from the history of science?John M. Nicholas - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):530-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Skinner's warnings still relevant to current psychology?Marc N. Richelle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):531-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Darwin and Darwin Studies, 1959–63.Bert James Loewenberg - 1965 - History of Science 4 (1):15-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Causal independence.Igal Kvart - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (1):96-114.
    In Kvart (1991a), I discussed the analysis of causal relevance presented in A Theory of Counterfactuals (1986) (and first in 1975). I explained there in what respect the notion captured by the analysis of Kvart (1986) is a mere approximation to the requisite notion of causal relevance. In this paper I present another analysis of causal relevance, devoid of the shortcoming of its predecessor. The present analysis of causal relevance is, again, grounded in a chancelike notion of objective probability. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reflections about the embeddedness of science, technology and society.Tatiana Schor - 2007 - Scientiae Studia 5 (3):337-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dark side of Skinnerian epistemology.William W. Rozeboom - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):533-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Positivism Is the Organizational Myth of Science.Stephan Fuchs - 1993 - Perspectives on Science 1 (1):1-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Behavioral and statistical theorists and their disciples.Leroy Wolins - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):540-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology: Toward the mathematical inner man.James T. Townsend - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior, theories, and the inner.Ernest Sosa - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):537-539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theoretical contingencies.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):541-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The question: Not shall it be, but which shall it be?Charles P. Shimp - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Theories and human behavior.Morton L. Schagrin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-536.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What then should we do?Seth Roberts - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):532-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner's philosophy of method.R. J. Nelson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):529-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive science: A different approach to scientific psychology.Richard Millward - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):527-529.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The challenge to Skinner's theory of behavior.Brian Mackenzie - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):526-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Buddhist Epistemology and Western Philosopy of Science.Elías Manuel Capriles - 2016 - Culture and Dialogue 4 (1):170-193.
    Buddhism has always produced epistemological systems, and those of the Mahāyāna, in particular, always showed knowledge and perception to be inherently delusive. “Higher” forms of Buddhism have a degenerative philosophy of history according to which a sort of Golden Age was disrupted by the rise and gradual development of knowledge and the delusion inherent in it, which have reached their apex in our time – the final phase of the “Era of Darkness.” From this standpoint, this paper intends to show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark