Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. An Explanatory Challenge to Moral Reductionism.Lei Zhong - 2012 - Theoria 78 (4):309-325.
    It is generally believed that moral reductionism is immune from notorious problems in moral metaphysics and epistemology, such as the problem of moral explanation – it is at least on this dimension that moral reductionism scores better than moral anti- reductionism. However, in this article I reject this popular view. First, I argue that moral reductionism fails to help vindicate the explanatory efficacy of moral properties because the reductionist solution is either circular or otiose. Second, I attempt to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Modeling the mind's eye.Lynn A. Cooper - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):550-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brain cartography: Electrical stimulation of processing sites or transmission lines?William E. Cooper - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):212-213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The explanatory virtue of abstracting away from idiosyncratic and messy detail.Christopher Clarke - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (6):1429-1449.
    Some explanations are relatively abstract: they abstract away from the idiosyncratic or messy details of the case in hand. The received wisdom in philosophy is that this is a virtue for any explanation to possess. I argue that the apparent consensus on this point is illusory. When philosophers make this claim, they differ on which of four alternative varieties of abstractness they have in mind. What’s more, for each variety of abstractness there are several alternative reasons to think that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • How to define levels of explanation and evaluate their indispensability.Christopher Clarke - 2017 - Synthese 194 (6).
    Some explanations in social science, psychology and biology belong to a higher level than other explanations. And higher explanations possess the virtue of abstracting away from the details of lower explanations, many philosophers argue. As a result, these higher explanations are irreplaceable. And this suggests that there are genuine higher laws or patterns involving social, psychological and biological states. I show that this ‘abstractness argument’ is really an argument schema, not a single argument. This is because the argument uses the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ojemann's data: Provocative but mysterious.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):211-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Timing sequencers as a foundation for language.William H. Calvin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):210-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurolinguistic and philosophical implications of electrical stimulation mapping of the human brain.Hugh W. Buckingham - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):209-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stimulation maps from the standpoint of aphasia study.Jason W. Brown - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):207-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurologizing mental imagery: the physiological optics of the mind's eye.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):550-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial life as it could be.Eric Bonabeau & Paul Bourgine - 1994 - World Futures 40 (4):227-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phrenology, 1982: What does it tell the aphasiologist?François Boller - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):207-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Matters of definition in the demystification of mental imagery.John S. Antrobus - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):549-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imagining the purpose of imagery.Robert P. Abelson - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):548-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Supervenience and Anomalism are Compatible.Oron Shagrir - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (2):241-266.
    I explore a Davidsonian proposal for the reconciliation of two theses. One is the supervenience of the mental on the physical, the other is the anomalism of the mental. The gist of the proposal is that supervenience and anomalism are theses about interpretation. Starting with supervenience, the claim is that it should not be understood in terms of deeper metaphysical relations, but as a constraint on the relations between the applications of physical and mental predicates. Regarding anomalism, the claim is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Anomalism and Supervenience: A Critical Survey.Oron Shagrir - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):237-272.
    The thesis that mental properties are dependent, or supervenient, on physical properties, but this dependence is not lawlike, has been influential in contemporary philosophy of mind. It is put forward explicitly in Donald Davidson's seminal ‘Mental Events.’ On the one hand, Davidson claims that the mental is anomalous, that ‘there are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained’ (1970, 208), and, in particular, that there are no strict psychophysical laws. On the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Anomalism and supervenience: A critical survey.Oron Shagrir - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):pp. 237-272.
    The thesis that mental properties are dependent, or supervenient, on physical properties, but this dependence is not lawlike, has been influential in contemporary philosophy of mind. It is put forward explicitly in Donald Davidson's seminal ‘Mental Events.’ On the one hand, Davidson claims that the mental is anomalous, that ‘there are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained’, and, in particular, that there are no strict psychophysical laws. On the other hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The New Mechanical Philosophy.Stuart Glennan - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This volume argues for a new image of science that understands both natural and social phenomena to be the product of mechanisms, casting the work of science as an effort to understand those mechanisms. Glennan offers an account of the nature of mechanisms and of the models used to represent them in physical, life, and social sciences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • The Putnam-McDowell Controversy on Perception and the Relevant Sciences.Yifeng Xu - 2021 - Philosophia 50 (2):787-814.
    A large part of Hilary Putnam’s latest work is spent on disagreeing with John McDowell’s conceptualist view of perception which has been expressed in Mind and World and the McDowellian disjunctivism. Nevertheless, Putnam does not articulate which specific aspects of McDowell’s view he disagrees with. This paper endeavours to: first, clarify what Putnam’s disagreement with McDowell precisely is based on an investigation of the views held by each of the two philosophers regarding the problem of the mind and perception, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cortical and thalamic representation of the episodic and semantic memory systems:Converging evidence from brain stimulation, local metabolic indicators, and human neuropsychology.Frank Wood - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):220-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causal depth, theoretical appropriateness, and individualism in psychology.Robert A. Wilson - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (1):55-75.
    Individualists claim that wide explanations in psychology are problematic. I argue that wide psychological explanations sometimes have greater explanatory power than individualistic explanations. The aspects of explanatory power I focus on are causal depth and theoretical appropriateness. Reflection on the depth and appropriateness of other wide explanations of behavior, such as evolutionary explanations, clarifies why wide psychological explanations sometimes have more causal depth and theoretical appropriateness than narrow psychological explanations. I also argue for the rejection of eliminative materialism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Explanatory Depth.Brad Weslake - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (2):273-294.
    I defend an account of explanatory depth according to which explanations in the non-fundamental sciences can be deeper than explanations in fundamental physics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • On the function of mental imagery.David L. Waltz - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):569-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A precise timing mechanism may underlie a common speech perception and production area in the peri-Sylvian cortex of the dominant hemisphere.Paula Tallal - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):219-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mapping speech: More analysis, less synthesis, please.Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):218-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On spatial symbols.William E. Smythe & Paul A. Kolers - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):568-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphor versus reality in the understanding of imagery: the path from function to structure.Peter W. Sheehan - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):567-568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why we view the brain as a computer.Oron Shagrir - 2006 - Synthese 153 (3):393-416.
    The view that the brain is a sort of computer has functioned as a theoretical guideline both in cognitive science and, more recently, in neuroscience. But since we can view every physical system as a computer, it has been less than clear what this view amounts to. By considering in some detail a seminal study in computational neuroscience, I first suggest that neuroscientists invoke the computational outlook to explain regularities that are formulated in terms of the information content of electrical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • The image-like and the language-like.Benny Shanon - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):566-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Al, imagery, and theories.Roger C. Schank - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):566-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On demystifying the mental for psychology.Edward Sankowski - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):565-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Do not adjust your mind, there is a fault in reality’— ideology in neurobiology.Steven P. R. Rose & Hilary Rose - 1973 - Cognition 2 (4):479-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causal Overdetermination and Kim’s Exclusion Argument.Michael Roche - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):809-826.
    Jaegwon Kim’s influential exclusion argument attempts to demonstrate the inconsistency of nonreductive materialism in the philosophy of mind. Kim’s argument begins by showing that the three main theses of nonreductive materialism, plus two additional considerations, lead to a specific and familiar picture of mental causation. The exclusion argument can succeed only if, as Kim claims, this picture is not one of genuine causal overdetermination. Accordingly, one can resist Kim’s conclusion by denying this claim, maintaining instead that the effects of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The demands of mental travel: demand characteristics of mental imagery experiments.Charles L. Richman, David B. Mitchell & J. Steven Reznick - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):564-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conscious and nonconscious imagery.Alan Richardson - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):563-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence: A Course Outline.William J. Rapaport - 1986 - Teaching Philosophy 9 (2):103-120.
    In the Fall of 1983, I offered a junior/senior-level course in Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, in the Department of Philosophy at SUNY Fredonia, after returning there from a year’s leave to study and do research in computer science and artificial intelligence (AI) at SUNY Buffalo. Of the 30 students enrolled, most were computerscience majors, about a third had no computer background, and only a handful had studied any philosophy. (I might note that enrollments have subsequently increased in the Philosophy Department’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Imagery theory: not mysterious – just wrong.Zenon Pylyshyn - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):561-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Computational versus operational approaches to imagery.Allan Paivio - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):561-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Task-specificity and species-specificity in the study of language: A methodological note.Daniel N. Osherson & Thomas Wasow - 1976 - Cognition 4 (2):203-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Brain organization for language from the perspective of electrical stimulation mapping.George A. Ojemann - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):189-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Electrical stimulation and the neurobiology of language.George A. Ojemann - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):221-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • On models, mechanisms and the evolution of human language.John D. Newman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):217-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some issues surrounding the reduction of macroeconomics to microeconomics.Alan Nelson - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (4):573–594.
    This paper examines the relationship between modern theories of microeconomics and macroeconomics and, more generally, it evaluates the prospects of theoretically reducing macroeconomics to microeconomics. Many economists have shown strong interest in providing "microfoundations" for macroeconomics and much of their work is germane to the issue of theoretical reduction. Especially relevant is the work that has been done on what is called The Problem of Aggregation. On some accounts, The Problem of Aggregation just is the problem of reducing macroeconomics to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Images, models, and human nature.Ulric Neisser - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):561-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The imprecision of mental imagery.Thomas P. Moran - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):560-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The effects of ventriloquism on the right-side advantage for verbal material.José Morais - 1974 - Cognition 3 (2):127-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neural models that convince: Model hierarchies and other strategies to bridge the gap between behavior and the brain.Martijn Meeter, Janneke Jehee & Jaap Murre - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (6):749 – 772.
    Computational modeling of the brain holds great promise as a bridge from brain to behavior. To fulfill this promise, however, it is not enough for models to be 'biologically plausible': models must be structurally accurate. Here, we analyze what this entails for so-called psychobiological models, models that address behavior as well as brain function in some detail. Structural accuracy may be supported by (1) a model's a priori plausibility, which comes from a reliance on evidence-based assumptions, (2) fitting existing data, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Skepticism and Elegance.Kevin McCain - 2016 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 6 (1):30-43.
    _ Source: _Page Count 14 Jonathan Vogel has argued in support of an explanationist response to skepticism in several works. Central to this explanationist response is the fact that our non-skeptical view of the world is a better explanation of our experiences than its skeptical rivals. Despite the plausibility of this response to skepticism, it is not without its critics. Recently, Matthew Gifford has argued that Vogel’s response has problems on two fronts. First, Gifford argues that Vogel’s strategy for showing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A rose by any other name.John C. Marshall - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):216-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A conceptual, an experimental, and a modeling question about imagery research.R. Duncan Luce - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):559-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark