Switch to: References

Citations of:

Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man

University Park, Pa.: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Derek R. Brookes & Knud Haakonssen (1785)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Epistemological Problems of Perception.Jack Lyons - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    An introductory overview of the main issues in the epistemology of perception.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Vera Causa Principle in the 18th Century Moral Philosophy.Fernando Morett - unknown
    David Hume has been largely read as a philosopher but not as a scientist. In this article I discuss his work exclusively as a case of science; in particular as a case of early modern science. I compare the moral psychology of self-interest, sympathy and sentiments of humanity he argues for with the moral psychology of universal self-interest from Bernard Mandeville, presenting the controversy between the two as a case of theory choice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reid on the first principles of morals.Terence Cuneo - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):102-121.
    What role do the first principles of morals play in Reid's moral theory? Reid has an official line regarding their role, which identifies these principles as foundational propositions that evidentially ground other moral propositions. I claim that, by Reid's own lights, this line of thought is mistaken. There is, however, another line of thought in Reid, one which identifies the first principles of morals as constitutive of moral thought. I explore this interpretation, arguing that it is a fruitful way of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Disagreement, design, and Thomas Reid.René van Woudenberg - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):224-239.
    This paper argues that Reid's first principle of design can be more widely accepted then one might suppose, due to the fact that it specifies no marks of design. Also it is explicated that the relation of the principle, on the one hand, and properly basic design beliefs on the other, is a relation of presupposition. It is furthermore suggested that Reid's discussion of what can be done in case of disagreement about first principles points to a position that is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reidian Dual Component Theory defended.Todd Buras - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):4-24.
    For Reid perception, broadly speaking, was a complex of two very different mental states. Calling such views dual component theory, A. D. Smith questions whether any such theory, and whether Reid's version in particular, is a viable theory of perception. The aim of this paper is to defend Reidian Dual Component Theory from Smith's critique. Answering Smith's critique reveals the depth and resilience of Reid's approach to perception, highlighting specifically the continued interest of his thought about the relationship between sensation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reid's response to Hume's perceptual relativity argument.Lorne Falkenstein - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):25-49.
    Reid declared Hume's appeal to variation in the magnitude of a table with distance to be the best argument that had ever been offered for the ‘ideal hypothesis’ that we experience nothing but our own mental states. Reid's principal objection to this argument fails to apply to minimally visible points. He did establish that we have reason to take our perceptions to be caused by external objects. But his case that we directly perceive external objects is undermined by what Hume (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reid on Powers of the Mind and the Person behind the Curtain.Laurent Jaffro - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):197-213.
    According to Thomas Reid, powers of will and powers of understanding are distinguishable in thought, but conjoined in practice. This paper examines the claim that there is no inert intelligence, the operations of the understanding involving some degree of activity. The question is: whose activity? For it is clear that a great deal of our mental activity is not in our power. We need to distinguish between a weak and a strong sense of ‘power’, and consider our dependence ‘upon God (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reid on Particularism, Habit, and Personal Identity.Jong Won Kim - 2015 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 13 (3):203-217.
    Are the first principles in the philosophy of Thomas Reid derived inductively from particular experience, or are they self-evident? Is Reid an epistemic particularist, or a methodist? Some scholars interpret him as an epistemic particularistic, while others hold that he is a methodist like other philosophers of his time. This debate was central to an exchange between Roderick Chisholm and Keith Lehrer. Taking the general belief in personal identity as an example, this paper aims to show which interpretation is more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reid’s Account of the “Geometry of Visibles”: Some Lessons from Helmholtz.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):485-510.
    Drawing on work done by Helmholtz, I argue that Reid was in no position to infer that objects appear as if projected on the inner surface of a sphere, or that they have the geometric properties of such projections even though they do not look concave towards the eye. A careful consideration of the phenomena of visual experience, as further illuminated by the practice of visual artists, should have led him to conclude that the sides of visible appearances either look (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Distance and Direction in Reid’s Theory of Vision.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):465-478.
    Two theses appear to be central to Reid’s view of the visual field. By sight, we do not originally perceive depth or linear distance from the eye. By sight, we originally perceive the position that points on the surface of objects have with regard to the centre of the eye. In different terms, by sight, we originally perceive the compass direction and degree of elevation of points on the surface of objects with reference to the centre of the eye. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does absence make atheistic belief grow stronger?Sarah Adams & Jon Robson - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 79 (1):49-68.
    Discussion of the role which religious experience can play in warranting theistic belief has received a great deal of attention within contemporary philosophy of religion. By contrast, the relationship between experience and atheistic belief has received relatively little focus. Our aim in this paper is to begin to remedy that neglect. In particular, we focus on the hitherto under-discussed question of whether experiences of God’s absence can provide positive epistemic status for a belief in God’s nonexistence. We argue that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Empirical Conditions for a Reidean Geometry of Visual Experience.Hannes Ole Matthiessen - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):511-522.
    Thomas Reid's Geometry of Visibles, according to which the geometrical properties of an object's perspectival appearance equal the geometrical properties of its projection on the inside of a sphere with the eye in its centre allows for two different interpretations. It may (1) be understood as a theory about phenomenal visual space – i.e. an account of how things appear to human observers from a certain point of view – or it may (2) be seen as a mathematical model of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sensuous Experience, Phenomenal Presence, and Perceptual Availability.Christopher Frey - 2015 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (2):237-254.
    I argue that an experience’s sensuous elements play an ineliminable role in our being intentionally directed upon an entity through perception. More specifically, I argue that whenever we appreciate a sensuous element in experience, we appreciate an intrinsic and irreducibly phenomenal aspect of experience that I call phenomenal presence – an aspect of experience that I show is central to its presentational character – and that the appreciation of phenomenal presence is necessary for perceptual intentionality. If an experience is to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Imperfect Identity.Eric T. Olson - 2006 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (2):81-98.
    Questions of identity over time are often hard to answer. A long tradition has it that such questions are somehow soft: they have no unique, determinate answer, and disagreements about them are merely verbal. I argue that this claim is not the truism it is taken to be. Depending on how it is understood, it turns out either to be false or to presuppose a highly contentious metaphysical claim.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reid, Hardness and Developmental Psychology.Adam Weiler Gur Arye - 2014 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 12 (2):145-162.
    I suggest two main ways of interpreting Reid's analysis of the perception of the quality of hardness: Reid endorses two distinct concepts of hardness. The distinction between the two lies in a profoundly different relation between the sensation of hardness and the concept of hardness in each of them. The first concept, which I term as a “sensation-laden concept”, is “the quality that arises in us the sensation of hardness.” The second concept, which I call a “non-sensational concept”, is “the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Relevance of Folk Intuitions to Philosophical Debates.Adam Feltz - 2008 - Dissertation, Florida State University
    A large portion of philosophy done in the Western analytic tradition attempts to provide conceptual analyses which are tested by examples that elicit intuitions. These intuitions are, in turn, used as evidence either for or against a given analysis. In recent years, there has been much discussion of the uses of intuitions from empirically minded philosophers and psychologists. The basic strategy is to discover empirically how “normal” folks think about certain topics in philosophy. This application of folk intuitions to philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Nature of Memory Traces.Felipe De Brigard - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (6):402-414.
    Memory trace was originally a philosophical term used to explain the phenomenon of remembering. Once debated by Plato, Aristotle, and Zeno of Citium, the notion seems more recently to have become the exclusive province of cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists. Nonetheless, this modern appropriation should not deter philosophers from thinking carefully about the nature of memory traces. On the contrary, scientific research on the nature of memory traces can rekindle philosopher's interest on this notion. With that general aim in mind, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Dualism in the Epistemology of Testimony and the Ability Intuition. [REVIEW]Spyridon Orestis Palermos - 2011 - Philosophia 39 (3):597-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Naturalized Female Intellect.Lorraine Daston - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (2):209-235.
    The ArgumentNaturalization confers authority on beliefs, conventions, and claims, but what kind of authority? Because the meaning of nature has a history, so does that of naturalization:naturalization is not the same tactic when marshaled in, say, eighteenth-century France and in late nineteenth-century Britain. Although the authority of nature may be invoked in both cases, the import of that authority depends crucially on whether nature is understood normatively or descriptively, within the framework of the natural laws of jurisprudence or within that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Justin Leiber, W. J. Talbott, Anthony Dardis, Dale Jamieson, Douglas Dempster, John Snapper, Denise Dellarosa Cummins, Michael Wheeler, Harry Heft, Donald Levy, Lindley Darden & Alastair Tait - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (4):389-431.
    Speaking: from Intention to Articulation Willem J. M. Levelt, 1989 (1993 paperback) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press ISBN: 0–262–12137–9(hb), 0–262–62089–8(pb)Rules for Reasoning Richard E. Nisbett (Ed.), 1993 Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates ISBN: 0–8058–1256–3(hb), 0–8085–1257–1 (pb)Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science Alvin I. Goldman, 1993 Cambridge, MA, MIT Press ISBN: 0–262–07153–3(hb), 0–262–57100–5(pb)Language Comprehension in Ape and Child, Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, Serial No. 233, Vol. 58, Nos 3–4 Sue Savage‐Rumbaugh, Jeannine Murphy, Rose A. Sevcik, Karen E. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reply to my critics.Bryan Caplan - 2008 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (3):377-413.
    This symposium’s objections to my book fall into two main categories: philosophical and empirical. The philosophical objections are largely sophistical. If we took them seriously, they would invalidate far more than my book: We would also have to give up social science and common sense. The empirical objections, in contrast, are often thoughtful and important. The most notable: Kiewiet and Mattozzi’s vigorous defense of the American public’s free‐trade credentials, and Wittman’s doubts about the magnitude of the belief gap between economists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Relativism about Truth and Predicates of Taste.Barry C. Smith - 2012 - Filosofia Unisinos 13 (2 - suppl.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Constancy in a changing world.Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):587-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Context effects in the entropic theory of perception.Kenneth H. Norwich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-579.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Selecting one attribute for judgment is not an act of stupidity.Robert Teghtsoonian - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):580-581.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Do we scale “objects” or isolated sensory dimensions?Michel Treisman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):581-584.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.J. van Brakel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):584-585.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Keeping the bath water along with the baby: Context effects represent a challenge, not a mortal wound, to the body of psychophysics.Mark Wagner - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):585-586.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Context effects: Pervasiveness and analysis.Donald L. King - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Will the real stimulus please step forward?Lester E. Krueger - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Two categories of contextual variable in perception.Donald Laming - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):572-573.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Covert converging operations for multidimensional psychophysics.Neil A. Macmillan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):573-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The perplexing plurality of psychophysical processes.Lawrence E. Marks - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):574-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysics and quantitative perceptual laws.Sergio C. Masin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):575-576.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How important are dimensions to perception?Robert D. Melara - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):576-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attributes or objects: A paradigm shift in psychophysics.John S. Monahan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):577-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The determinants of perceived brightness are complicated, but not hopelessly so.Thomas R. Corwin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):564-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can brightness be related to luminance by a meaningful function?Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):565-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The complexity and importance of the psychophysical scaling of sensory attributes.George A. Gescheider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Scales falling from the eyes?Richard L. Gregory - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Walking in a psychophysical dustbowl creates a dustcloud.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):568-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysics: Plus ça change ….Peter R. Killeen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):569-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysical scaling within an information processing approach?Claude Bonnet - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Psychophysical scaling: To describe relations or to uncover a law?Gunnar Borg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):561-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Accounting for an old inconsistency in the psychophysics of Plateau and Delboeuf.Marc Brysbaert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):562-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Psychophysical scaling: Context and illusion.Stanley Coren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):563-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Perception, apperception and psychophysics.Daniel Algom - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):558-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Integration psychophysics is not traditional psychophysics.Norman H. Anderson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):559-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations