Switch to: References

Citations of:

Collected Papers

Philosophical Books 13 (1):29-32 (1972)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Not thinking about the same thing. Enactivism, pragmatism and intentionality.Pierre Steiner - forthcoming - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences:1-24.
    Enactivism does not have its primary philosophical roots in pragmatism: phenomenology (from Husserl to Jonas) is its first source of inspiration (with the exception of Hutto & Myin’s radical enactivism). That does not exclude the benefits of pragmatist readings of enactivism, and of enactivist readings of pragmatism. After having sketched those readings, this paper focuses on the philosophical concept of intentionality. I show that whereas enactivists endorse the idea that intentionality is a base-level property of cognition, pragmatism offer(ed) us some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In defense of ordinary language philosophy.Herman Cappelen & Matthew McKeever - 2022 - Metaphilosophy 53 (2-3):221-237.
    Metaphilosophy, Volume 53, Issue 2-3, Page 221-237, April 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Moral Testimony, Knowledge and Understanding.Kumar Viswanathan - 2021 - Philosophical Investigations 45 (3):297-319.
    Philosophical Investigations, Volume 45, Issue 3, Page 297-319, July 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato’s Theaetetus and the Hunting of the Proposition.Lesley Brown - 2020 - Rhizomata 8 (2):268-288.
    Section 1 contrasts the approaches to Plato of F.M.Cornford and Gilbert Ryle, two of the early twentieth century’s leading Plato interpreters. Then I trace and evaluate attempts to discern in Plato’s Theaetetus a recognition of the role of the proposition. Section 2 focuses on the hunting of the proposition in Socrates’ Dream in the Theaetetus. Ryle, inspired by Logical Atomism, argued that Plato there anticipated an insight about the difference between names and propositions that Russell credited to Wittgenstein. I rehearse (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From the Heterogeneity Problem to a Natural‐Kind Approach to Pleasure.Antonin Broi - 2023 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 104 (2):274-300.
    The heterogeneity problem, which stems from the alleged difficulty of finding out what all pleasant experiences have in common, is largely considered as a substantial issue in the philosophy of pleasure, one that is usually taken as the starting point for theorizing about the essence of pleasure. The goal of this paper is to move the focus away from the heterogeneity problem and toward an alternative approach to pleasure. To do this, I first show that, although the approach stemming from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norms and Necessity.Amie L. Thomasson - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (2):143-160.
    Modality presents notorious philosophical problems, including the epistemic problem of how we could come to know modal facts and metaphysical problems about how to place modal facts in the natural world. These problems arise from thinking of modal claims as attempts to describe modal features of this world that explain what makes them true. Here I propose a different view of modal discourse in which talk about what is “metaphysically necessary” does not aim to describe modal features of the world, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Kant on anthropology and alienology: The opacity of human motivation and its anthropological implications.Alix Cohen - 2008 - Kantian Review 13 (2):85-106.
    According to Kant, the opacity of human motivation takes two distinct forms – a psychological form: man ‘can never, even by the most strenuous self-examination, get entirely behind [his] covert incentives’ – and a social form: ‘everyone in our race finds it advisable to be on his guard, and not to reveal himself completely’. In other words, first, men's ‘interior’ cannot be entirely revealed to themselves and, second, they tend not to reveal their ‘interior’ to others. A number of Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • XIII—Knowing How to Reason Logically.Corine Besson - 2021 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 121 (3):327-353.
    In this paper, I examine Gilbert Ryle’s claim that ordinary competence with logical principles or rules is a kind of knowing how, where such knowledge is understood as a skill, a multi-track disposition. Ryle argues that his account of ordinary logical competence helps avoid Lewis Carroll’s famous regress argument (Carroll 1895), which suggests that elementary deductive reasoning might be impossible. Indeed, Carroll’s regress is the central motivation for Ryle’s account. I argue that this account is inadequate on two counts: it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Thick Records and Complex Artworks: A Study of Record-Keeping Practices at the Museum.Yaël Kreplak - 2018 - Human Studies 41 (4):697-717.
    In 1967 Garfinkel and Bittner were investigating good organizational reasons for bad clinic records, demonstrating how the reading of such records as sociological data should be reported to the understanding of their production’s practical contingencies and to the situated circumstances of their use. This seminal paper opened new avenues of research related to the study of records in various professional contexts and of their transformation, to the development of praxiological approaches to practical and professional texts, or to the study of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of the modern mind. Some remarks on Dewey's "Unmodern philosophy and modern philosophy".Pierre Steiner - 2013 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 5 (1).
    In Unmodern Philosophy and Modern Philosophy, Dewey develops a comprehensive account of mindedness and a genealogical picture of the modern concept of ‘mind.’ Chapter X, “Mind and Body”, is the longest chapter of the book. Its three sections correspond to three different folders, yet all written in 1942. The title of the chapter – Dewey’s own title – might sound surprising to the readers of chapter VII of Experience and Nature, where Dewey explicitly coined the term ‘body-min...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wilderness, cultivation and appropriation.John O'Neill - 2002 - Philosophy and Geography 5 (1):35 – 50.
    "Nature" and "wilderness" are central normative categories of environmentalism. Appeal to those categories has been subject to two lines of criticism: from constructivists who deny there is something called "nature" to be defended; from the environmental justice movement who point to the role of appeals to "nature" and "wilderness" in the appropriation of land of socially marginal populations. While these arguments often come together they are independent. This paper develops the second line of argument by placing recent appeals to "wilderness" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The teaching of skills and the skills of teaching: A reply to Robin Barrow.Morwenna Griffiths - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (2):203–214.
    Morwenna Griffiths; The Teaching of Skills and the Skills of Teaching: a reply to Robin Barrow, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 2, 30 May 2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Socrates' dream.Stanley Rosen - 1976 - Theoria 42 (1-3):161-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Conspiracy Theory’ as a Tonkish Term: Some Runabout Inference-Tickets from Truth to Falsehood.Charles Pigden - 2023 - Social Epistemology 37 (4):423-437.
    I argue that ‘conspiracy theory’ and ‘conspiracy theorist’ as commonly employed are ‘tonkish’ terms (as defined by Arthur Prior and Michael Dummett), licensing inferences from truths to falsehoods; indeed, that they are mega-tonkish terms, since their use is governed by different and competing sets of introduction and elimination rules, delivering different and inconsistent results. Thus ‘conspiracy theory’ and ‘conspiracy theorist’ do not have determinate extensions, which means that generalizations about conspiracy theories or conspiracy theorists do not have determinate truth-values. Hence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Gettier und kein Ende? Das doxastische Dogma der modernen Wissenstheorie.Rainer Enskat - 2015 - Angewandte Philosophie. Eine Internationale Zeitschrift 2 (1):115-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speaking and Signifying.William Charlton - 2019 - Philosophy 94 (1):3-25.
    After a brief introduction I compare accounts of what it is to say something I find in Plato, Frege and Grice, and I distinguish linguistic from practical meaning and words that signify things from ‘syncategorematic’ or ‘grammatical’ words. I then argue that the relation between a signifying word and what it signifies must be understood in terms of two complementary acts, already recognised in antiquity, quantifying and predicating. Discussing quantification, I show how problems about universals can be avoided by accepting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-Factualist Dispositionalism.Manuel Heras-Escribano - 2017 - Philosophia 45 (2):607-629.
    This paper aims to defend that the best framework for characterizing dispositions is a Rylean, non-factualist dispositionalism. I follow Tugby, 451–480, 2013) in explaining which are the main candidates for characterizing the ontology of dispositions. Tugby, 451–480, 2013) concludes that the best metaphysical framework for characterizing dispositions is Platonism, because it is the only theory that can account for the central and the intrinsic platitudes. Following this I show that Platonism is not desirable because it is difficult to reconcile with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Embodied reflection and the epistemology of reflective practice.Elizabeth Anne Kinsella - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (3):395–409.
    Donald Schön’s theory of reflective practice has been extensively referred to and has had enormous impact in education and related fields. Nonetheless, there continues to be tremendous conceptual and practical confusion surrounding interpretations of reflective practice and philosophical assumptions underlying the theory. In this paper, I argue that one of the original contributions of reflective practice is the theory’s attention to an embodied reflective dimension. In this regard, the influences of Michael Polanyi and Gilbert Ryle, within Donald Schön’s classic work, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Truth and Knowledge in F. P. Ramsey’s Essays: a Pragmatic Overview.Antonio Lizzadri - 2022 - Acta Analytica 37 (4):489-505.
    This paper aims to renew the “deflationary” interpretation of Ramsey’s theory of truth, with respect to his declared “pragmatist tendency,” which was not completely developed due to his premature death. This aim is not only historical-philosophical, but also exquisitely theoretical, since the mediation of pragmatism allowed Ramsey to achieve an original synthesis among different philosophical instances. In order to show this, I pay attention to the debate between Ramsey and some spokespeople of the leading British philosophical traditions at the beginning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phronesis in musical performance.Jan W. O’Dea - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):233–243.
    ABSTRACT This paper suggests a much more serious purpose for an education in music-making than play or pleasure or even the training of professional musicians. It presents and explicates a possible connection between musical performance training and the development of practical wisdom. Music in performance constitutes in effect a form of virtuous conduct, where one learns through doing and thereafter comes to love and to be capable of wise practical judgement. Excellence in this field requires the exercise of a species (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Skeptical challenges and knowing actions.Stephen Hetherington - 2013 - Philosophical Issues 23 (1):18-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ryle and Collingwood: Their correspondence and its philosophical context.Charlotte Vrijen - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (1):93 – 131.
    *I would like to thank Michel ter Hark, Lodi Nauta and James Connelly, for their critical reading of earlier versions of this paper and for their comments. Gilbert Ryle and R. G. Collingwood are no...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ryle’s Logical Geography of Perception Verbs.Annemarie Kalis - 2024 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 101 (2):141-159.
    Gilbert Ryle’s account of perception has not become widely known. Moreover, most of the responses to his account have been critical. Ryle’s method was to analyze our everyday use of perception verbs such as ‘seeing’ and ‘hearing’, in order to argue that perception is a skill that we learn by doing. His critics concluded that by focusing on the use of perception verbs, Ryle dodged all central problems of perception. The current article aims to rebut this conclusion, by showing how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cartography of the Phenomenon and the Phenomenon as Cartography.Guilherme Riscali - 2017 - Phainomenon 26 (1):217-232.
    This paper discusses Gilbert Ryle’s image of philosophy as cartography in an attempt to explore the idea of a cartography of the phenomenon, confronting it with the sense it takes in Edmund Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology. Ryle tries to grasp the particularity of philosophical tasks as being about specific sorts of problems, not about specific sorts of objects. What is required both of a cartographer and of a philosopher is, according to him, to look at familiar spaces in wholly unusual terms. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A new disease of the intellect? Some reflections on the therapeutic value of Peter Winch’s philosophy for social and cultural studies of science.Michael Lynch - 2000 - History of the Human Sciences 13 (1):140-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Non-indexical action.James Heap - 1975 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (3):393-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What is Phenomenology?Simon Glendinning - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 3 (1):30-50.
    Simon Glendinning explains the mysteries of phenomenology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the theoretical foundations of the ‘Philosophy for Children’ programme.Florian Franken Figueiredo - 2022 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 56 (2):210-226.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 56, Issue 2, Page 210-226, April 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gilbert Ryle: A Mediator between Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology.Johannes L. Brandl - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1):143-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations