Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Pain and parallel processing.Ronald Melzack - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):67-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three frames suffice.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):296-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pain's composite wheel of woe.George Graham - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):60-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does connectionism suffice?Steven W. Zucker - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):301-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Pain is three-dimensional, inner, and occurrent.Keith Campbell - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):56-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Internal events as behavior, not causes.Daniel J. Bernstein - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):55-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heuristically, “pain” is mainly in the brain.W. Crawford Clark - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):57-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there always a neurochemical link between pain and behavior?G. Pepeu - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):69-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On computer science, visual science, and the physiological utility of models.Barry J. Richmond & Michael E. Goldberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):300-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Reliable computation in parallel networks.Keith Oatley - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):299-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Head-centered coordinates and the stable feature frame.Richard A. Andersen - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):289-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linking features in dimensions of mind and brain.Robert B. Glassman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):293-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tunnel vision will not suffice.Jerome A. Feldman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):302-313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three frames suffice: Drop the retinotopic frame.Ralph Norman Haber - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):295-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A mentalistic view of “Pain and behavior”.H. Merskey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):68-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Skinner's warnings still relevant to current psychology?Marc N. Richelle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):531-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bob Solomon and William James: A Rapprochement.Jenefer M. Robinson - 2010 - Emotion Review 2 (1):53-60.
    Bob Solomon used to inveigh against William James’ theory of emotions, but he eventually arrived at a rapprochement with James and James’s recent successors. In particular, James suggested that emotions are initiated by the “automatic, instinctive” appraisals that register important information in the body and are recorded by body-mapping brain areas. In recent work Solomon describes the judgments he thinks constitute emotions as felt bodily appraisals in similar fashion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Self-in-a-Vat: On John Searle's Ontology of Reasons for Acting.Kaufmann Laurence - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4):447-479.
    John Searle has recently developed a theory of reasons for acting that intends to rescue the freedom of the will, endangered by causal determinism, whether physical or psychological. To achieve this purpose, Searle postulates a series of “gaps” that are supposed toendowthe self with free will. Reviewing key steps in Searle's argument, this article shows that such an undertaking cannot be successfully completed because of its solipsist premises. The author argues that reasons for acting do not have a subjective, I-ontology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Social externalism and the ontology of competence.Andrew Davis - 2005 - Philosophical Explorations 8 (3):297-308.
    Social externalism implies that many competences are not personal assets separable from social and cultural environments but complex states of affairs involving individuals and persisting features of social reality. The paper explores the consequences for competence identity over time and across contexts, and hence for the predictive role usually accorded to competences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Oneindige regressieargumenten.Jan Willem Wieland - 2013 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 105 (1):1-14.
    Infinite regress arguments show up in many philosophical debates. But what actually is a regress argument? This article reviews two theories: the Paradox Theory and the Failure Theory. According to the Paradox Theory, regress arguments can be used to refute an existentially or universally quantified statement (e.g. to refute the statement that at least one discussion is settled, or the statement that discussions are settled only if there is an agreed-upon criterion to settle them). According to the Failure Theory, regress (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Skeptical challenges and knowing actions.Stephen Hetherington - 2013 - Philosophical Issues 23 (1):18-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Phenomenological Additions to the Bourdieusian Toolbox: Two Problems for Bourdieu, Two Solutions from Schutz.Will Atkinson - 2010 - Sociological Theory 28 (1):1-19.
    In constructing his renowned theory of practice, Pierre Bourdieu claimed to have integrated the key insights from phenomenology and successfully melded them with objectivist analysis. The contention here, however, is that while his vision of the social world may indeed be generally laudable, he did not take enough from phenomenology. More specifically, there are two concepts in Alfred Schutz 's body of work, which, if properly defined, disentangled from phenomenology, and appropriated, allow two frequently forwarded criticisms of Bourdieu's perspective to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Private Events.Max Hocutt - 2009 - Behavior and Philosophy 37:105 - 117.
    What are "private events" and what is their significance? The term is B. F. Skinner's, but the idea is much older. Before J. B. Watson challenged their methods and their metaphysics, virtually all psychologists assumed that the only way to discover a person's supposedly private states of mind was to ask her about them. Not a believer in minds, Skinner nevertheless agreed that sensations, feelings, and certain unspecified forms of "covert behavior" cannot be observed by others, because they take place (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Blind-Spot Argument Against Dispositionalist Accounts of Belief.Davide Fassio - 2014 - Acta Analytica 29 (1):71-81.
    Dispositionalist accounts of belief define beliefs in terms of specific sets of dispositions. In this article, I provide a blind-spot argument against these accounts. The core idea of the argument is that beliefs having the form [p and it is not manifestly believed that p] cannot be manifestly believed. This means that one cannot manifest such beliefs in one’s assertions, conscious thoughts, actions, behaviours, or any other type of activity. However, if beliefs are sets of dispositions, they must be manifestable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Of Counterfeits and Delusions: Revisiting Ryle on Skepticism and the Impossibility of Global Deceit.Douglas McDermid - 2004 - Disputatio 1 (17):1 - 23.
    Consider the following proposition: It is possible that all of our perceptual experiences are ‘delusive.’ According to Gilbert Ryle, is demonstrably absurd. In this paper I address four questions: What is Ryle’s argument against?; How persuasive is it?; What positions are ruled out if is absurd?; and How does Ryle’s position compare with contemporary work on skepticism?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ill Health or Illness: A Reply to Hofmann. [REVIEW]Lennart Nordenfelt - 2013 - Health Care Analysis 21 (4):298-305.
    In this article I respond to Björn Hofmann’s criticism of some elements in my theory of health. Hofmann’s main objective is to question “Nordenfelt’s basic premise that you can be ill without having negative first-person experiences, and to investigate the consequences of abandoning the premise.” One of Hofmann’s critical points is that my theory of health does not lend voice to the individual. My response is essentially conducted in four steps: (1) I question the aim of conceptual analysis that Hofmann (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Body and the Arts: The Need for Somaesthetics.Richard Shusterman - 2012 - Diogenes 59 (1-2):7-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A puzzle about mental self-representation and causation.Mikkel Gerken - 2014 - Philosophical Psychology 27 (6):890-906.
    The paper articulates a puzzle that consists in the prima facie incompatibility between three widely accepted theses. The first thesis is, roughly, that there are intrinsically selfrepresentational thoughts. The second thesis is, roughly, that there is a particular causal constraint on mental representation. The third thesis is, roughly, that nothing causes itself. In this paper, the theses are articulated in a less rough manner with the occurrence of the puzzle as a result. Finally, a number of solution strategies are considered, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ainda existe consciência?Renato Rodrigues Kinouchi - 2004 - Scientiae Studia 2 (3):415-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La partie, le tout et l'equilibration.Jacques Vonèche & Silvia Parrat-Dayan - 1994 - Philosophica 54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Stanley’s Intellectualism.J. Adam Carter - 2012 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (5):749-762.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ascriptions of propositional attitudes. An analysis in terms of intentional objects.Hans-Ulrich Hoche & Michael Knoop - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (4):747-768.
    Having briefly sketched the aims of our paper, namely, to logically analyse the ascription of propositional attitudes to somebody else in terms, not of Fregean senses or of intensions-with-s, but of the intentional object of the person spoken about, say, the believer or intender (Section 1), we try to introduce the concept of an intentional object as simply as possible, to wit, as coming into view whenever two (or more) subjective belief-worlds strikingly diverge (Section 2). Then, we assess the pros (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Knowledge of essence: the conferralist story.Ásta Kristjana Sveinsdóttir - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 166 (1):21-32.
    Realist essentialists face a prima facie challenge in accounting for our knowledge of the essences of things, and in particular, in justifying our engaging in thought experiments to gain such knowledge. In contrast, conferralist essentialism has an attractive story to tell about how we gain knowledge of the essences of things, and how thought experiments are a justified method for gaining such knowledge. The conferralist story is told in this essay.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Privileged Access and the Status of Self-Knowledge in Cartesian and Freudian Conceptions of the Mental.Morris Eagle - 1982 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 12 (4):349-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Haunted by the Ghost in the Machine. Commentary on “The Spirituality of Human Consciousness: A Catholic Evaluation of Some Current Neuro-scientific Interpretations”.James B. Miller - 2012 - Science and Engineering Ethics 18 (3):503-507.
    Metaphysical and epistemological dualism informs much contemporary discussion of the relationships of science and religion, in particular in relation to the neurosciences and the religious understanding of the human person. This dualism is a foundational artifact of modern culture; however, contemporary scientific research and historical theological scholarship encourage a more holistic view wherein human personhood is most fittingly understood as an emergent phenomenon of, but not simply reducible to, evolutionary and developmental neurobiology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Practising to Know: Practicalism and Confucian Philosophy.Stephen Hetherington & Karyn Lai - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (3):375-393.
    For a while now, there has been much conceptual discussion about the respective natures of knowledge-that and knowledge-how, along with the intellectualist idea that knowledge-how is really a kind of knowledge-that. Gilbert Ryle put in place most of the terms that have so far been distinctive of that debate, when he argued for knowledge-how's conceptual distinctness from knowledge-that. But maybe those terms should be supplemented, expanding the debate. In that spirit, the conceptual option of practicalism has recently entered the fray. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Horizontal and vertical determination of mental and neural states.Jens Harbecke & Harald Atmanspacher - 2012 - Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 32 (3):161-179.
    Mental and neural states are related to one another by vertical interlevel relations and by horizontal intralevel relations. For particular choices of such relations, problems arise if causal efficacy is ascribed to mental states. In a series of influential papers and books, Kim has presented his much discussed “supervenience argument,” which ultimately amounts to the dilemma that mental states either are causally inefficacious or they hold the threat of overdetermining neural states. Forced by this disjunction, Kim votes in favor of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Education for Computers.Robert D. Heslep - 2011 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 31 (4):357-364.
    The computer engineers who refer to the education of computers do not have a definite idea of education and do not bother to justify the fuzzy ones to which they allude. Hence, they logically cannot specify the features a computer must have in order to be educable. This paper puts forth a non-standard, but not arbitrary, concept of education that determines such traits. The proposed concept is derived from the idea of education embedded in modern standard-English discourse. Because the standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nature, reasons, and moral meaningfulness.Pierre Charette - unknown
    The "anthropology of moral life", or "moral anthropology", is an approach to moral philosophy which I take to have been initiated by Peter Strawson, and developed, independently and in different ways, by David Wiggins and Daniel Dennett. I take the respective moral anthropologies of Wiggins and Dennett to be complementary, and I propose to synthesize them within a Dennettian framework. The framework involves the definition of a "rationally acceptable language". Descriptions and accounts stated in that language are ontologically interpreted in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three Views of Language & the Mind.Submitted May - unknown
    The essay which follows is about the relationship between mind and language. Most recent thought about intentionality has it that (i) mental states of individuals are largely, or in the most fundamental cases, independent of social facts about public languages, and (ii) these social facts are derived from, or constituted by, the mental states of individuals. The purpose of this essay is to challenge this individualist orthodoxy (as well as the view of the relationship between mind and action which often (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dispositions : les attribuer ou les réduire ?Jean-Maurice Monnoyer - 2002 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 4 (4):443-460.
    Les dispositions sont de plusieurs sortes (physiques, artefactuelles, psychologiques). Pour cerner ce genre d’entités, nous sommes contraints d’user de prédicats et d’expressions conditionnelles. Le problème métaphysique naît de la nature même des conditionnels contrefactuels qui n’aident pas à capturer complètement la réalité de ce genre de propriétés. Une distinction paraît s’imposer entre la base d’une disposition et ses manifestations, mais elle ouvre à de nouvelles difficultés évoquées ici. En termes contemporains, cette distinction pourrait se voir déplacée à travers la séparation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Does One Know What Shame Is? Epistemology, Emotions, and Forms of Life in Juxtaposition.Ullaliina Lehtinen - 1998 - Hypatia 13 (1):56 - 77.
    Do women conceptualize-understand, know about, and react to-shame differently from the way men do? Does the experience and knowledge of shame have a gender-specificity, and along what lines could it be analyzed? By introducing a distinction between life or enduring experiences, "Erfahrung," and episodic or occurrent experiences, "Erlebnis," and by juxtaposing this distinction with the Rylean notion that knowledge is dispositional this paper argues for the plausibility of a gender-specificity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Believing Things.Robert C. Coburn - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):93 - 103.
    The account of belief adumbrated by Ryle in The Concept of Mind is, I think, a very tempting one despite its relative vagueness. According to this account, a belief that such and such is the case is a disposition of a certain kind. More specifically, it is a tendency or a propensity to behave and to react in more or less definite ways under certain circumstances. Thus “to believe that the ice is dangerously thin,” Ryle writes, “is to be unhesitant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ways and Means.Annetie C. Baier - 1972 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (3):275 - 293.
    In this paper I shall give reasons for rejecting one type of analysis of the basic constituents of action, and reasons for preferring an alternative approach. I shall discuss the concept of basic action recently presented by Alvin Goldman, who gives an interesting version of the sort of analysis I wish to reject. Goldman agrees with Danto that bodily movements are basic actions, and his definition of ‘basic’ resembles Danto's fairly closely. What is new is a useful concept of level-generation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Our Knowledge and Our Language.Robert X. Ware - 1973 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):153 - 168.
    I am not sure how confident we can be about our knowledge of the meaning of a sentence, but I am sure that we should be much less confident than we often are about the meaning of a word or non-sentential expression. This paper is an attempt to whittle away our confidence about word-meaning, and it is to this end that I investigate the meaning of the word ‘know'. But the point of the investigation is to show that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Disposition and Occurrence.Hung Hin-Chung - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):123 - 135.
    Can ‘disposition’ be understood as a contrast term, the contrast being ‘occurrence'? Put it another way: do ‘dispositional predicate’ and ‘occurrent predicate’ form a contrast pair? I shall show that if ‘occurrent’ is taken as simply meaning ‘non-dispositional', then ‘occurrent’ has no applications. However, if ‘occurrent’ is given an independent meaning so that predicates like ‘break', ‘bend', ‘disintegrate’ etc. are occurrent predicates, then it is not the contrast of ‘dispositional'. Its contrast is rather what I shall call ‘remainant’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mannison's Impossible Dream.Peter Preuss - 1976 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (3):535 - 542.
    Alastair Hannay wrote that there is a campaign against the mental image and a look at the philosophical literature on that topic bears him out. But there is also a campaign against dreams. Given the first campaign this is not surprising. What is surprising is that they are separate campaigns. Intuitively mental images and dreams seem to be as alike as kittens and cats, the one being merely the developed form of the other, made possible by the fading of consciousness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intention and Volition.Jing Zhu - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2):175 - 193.
    The volitional theory of human action has formed a basis for a prominent account of voluntary behavior since at least Aquinas. But in the twentieth century the notions of will and volition lost much of their popularity in both philosophy and psychology. Gilbert Ryle’s devastating attack on the concept of will, and especially the doctrine of volition, has had lingering effects evident in the widespread hostility and skepticism towards the will and volition. Since the 1970s, however, the volitional theory has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • My Papers - and Other Things.Aaron Sloman - unknown
    I am populating this file from the bottom up. Later years are still empty. Try stuff in or before 1998 for a start. My Oxford DPhil Thesis (1962) is the oldest item available here.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to Collaborate: Procedural Knowledge in the Cooperative Development of Science.Paul Thagard - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):177-196.
    This paper argues that collaboration in scientific and other fields requires a substantial amount of procedural knowledge about how to collaborate. It discusses how scientists collaborate, how they learn to collaborate, and why they collaborate. Knowledge how does not always reduce to knowledge that, and collaboration has many purposes besides the pursuit of power and resources. The relative scarcity of philosophical collaborations can be overcome by more naturalistic approaches to philosophy and by philosophers learning how to collaborate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations