Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Erich Kretschmann as a proto-logical-empiricist: Adventures and misadventures of the point-coincidence argument.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (2):115-134.
    The present paper attempts to show that a 1915 article by Erich Kretschmann must be credited not only for being the source of Einstein’s point-coincidence remark, but also for having anticipated the main lines of the logical-empiricist interpretation of general relativity. Whereas Kretschmann was inspired by the work of Mach and Poincaré, Einstein inserted Kretschmann’s point-coincidence parlance into the context of Ricci and Levi-Civita’s absolute differential calculus. Kretschmann himself realized this and turned the point-coincidence argument against Einstein in his second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • False Vacuum: Early Universe Cosmology and the Development of Inflation.Chris Smeenk - 2005 - In Eisenstaedt Jean & Knox A. J. (eds.), The Universe of General Relativity. Birkhauser. pp. 223-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Forgotten Tradition: How the Logical Empiricists Missed the Philosophical Significance of the Work of Riemann, Christoffel and Ricci.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (6):1219-1257.
    This paper attempts to show how the logical empiricists’ interpretation of the relation between geometry and reality emerges from a “collision” of mathematical traditions. Considering Riemann’s work as the initiator of a 19th century geometrical tradition, whose main protagonists were Helmholtz and Poincaré, the logical empiricists neglected the fact that Riemann’s revolutionary insight flourished instead in a non-geometrical tradition dominated by the works of Christoffel and Ricci-Curbastro roughly in the same years. I will argue that, in the attempt to interpret (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • `Nature is the Realisation of the Simplest Conceivable Mathematical Ideas': Einstein and the Canon of Mathematical Simplicity.John D. Norton - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (2):135-170.
    Einstein proclaimed that we could discover true laws of nature by seeking those with the simplest mathematical formulation. He came to this viewpoint later in his life. In his early years and work he was quite hostile to this idea. Einstein did not develop his later Platonism from a priori reasoning or aesthetic considerations. He learned the canon of mathematical simplicity from his own experiences in the discovery of new theories, most importantly, his discovery of general relativity. Through his neglect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Hilbert's 'foundations of physics': Gravitation and electromagnetism within the axiomatic method.K. A. Brading & T. A. Ryckman - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1):102-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Tuning up mind's pattern to nature's own idea: Eddington's early twenties case for variational derivatives.Ivahn Smadja - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 41 (2):128-145.
    This paper sets out to show how Eddington's early twenties case for variational derivatives significantly bears witness to a steady and consistent shift in focus from a resolute striving for objectivity towards “selective subjectivism” and structuralism. While framing his so-called “Hamiltonian derivatives” along the lines of previously available variational methods allowing to derive gravitational field equations from an action principle, Eddington assigned them a theoretical function of his own devising in The Mathematical Theory of Relativity (1923). I make clear that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Which symmetry? Noether, Weyl, and conservation of electric charge.Katherine A. Brading - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 (1):3-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Mass‐energy‐momentum: Only there because of spacetime.Dennis Lehmkuhl - 2011 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (3):453-488.
    I describe how relativistic field theory generalizes the paradigm property of material systems, the possession of mass, to the requirement that they have a mass–energy–momentum density tensor T µ associated with them. I argue that T µ does not represent an intrinsic property of matter. For it will become evident that the definition of T µ depends on the metric field g µ in a variety of ways. Accordingly, since g µ represents the geometry of spacetime itself, the properties of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Why history matters to philosophy of physics.Thomas Ryckman - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 50:4-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The principle of least action as the logical empiricist's shibboleth.Michael Stöltzner - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34 (2):285-318.
    The present paper investigates why logical empiricists remained silent about one of the most philosophy-laden matters of theoretical physics of their day, the principle of least action (PLA). In the two decades around 1900, the PLA enjoyed a remarkable renaissance as a formal unification of mechanics, electrodynamics, thermodynamics, and relativity theory. Taking Ernst Mach's historico-critical stance, it could be liberated from much of its physico-theological dross. Variational calculus, the mathematical discipline on which the PLA was based, obtained a new rigorous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Outline of a dynamical inferential conception of the application of mathematics.Tim Räz & Tilman Sauer - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 49:57-72.
    We outline a framework for analyzing episodes from the history of science in which the application of mathematics plays a constitutive role in the conceptual development of empirical sciences. Our starting point is the inferential conception of the application of mathematics, recently advanced by Bueno and Colyvan. We identify and discuss some systematic problems of this approach. We propose refinements of the inferential conception based on theoretical considerations and on the basis of a historical case study. We demonstrate the usefulness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Hilbert's axiomatic method and Carnap's general axiomatics.Michael Stöltzner - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 53:12-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematics and Physics: The Idea of a Pre-Established Harmony.Helge Kragh - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (5-6):515-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In das Deutschland „von Hilbert und Einstein”. Briefe von Einstein, Planck, Nernst, Debye, Born, Sommerfeld, Courant, Ehrenfest,Weyl und Althoff an David Hilbert, gefunden auf einem Göttinger Dachboden.Klaus P. Sommer - 2005 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 28 (4):283-303.
    Into the Germany “of Hilbert and Einstein”: Letters of Einstein, Planck, Nernst, Debye, Born, Sommerfeld, Courant, Ehrenfest, Weyl and Althoff to David Hilbert found in an attic in Göttingen. Abraham Pais described the discovery of Einstein's letters to Hilbert as “Helen's most important single contribution to the archives”1. Helen Dukas, of the Einstein Archive, had in fact only received photocopies. The location of the originals was unknown. The author first came across this correspondence between Hilbert and Einstein as well as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Electromagnetic Conception of Nature at the Root of the Special and General Relativity Theories and its Revolutionary Meaning.Enrico R. A. Giannetto - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (6-7):765-781.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations