Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Pain behavior: How to define the operant.Hugh Lacey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):64-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Folding of a peptide continuum: Semiotic approach to protein folding.Ľudmila Lacková - 2020 - Semiotica 2020 (233):77-90.
    In this paper I attempt to study the notion of “folding of a semiotic continuum” in a direction of a possible application to the biological processes. More specifically, the process of obtaining protein structures is compared in this paper to the folding of a semiotic continuum. Consequently, peptide chain is presented as a continuous line potential to be formed in order to create functional units. The functional units are protein structures having certain function in the cell or organism. Moreover, protein (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Language equals mimesis plus speech.Aarre Laakso - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):765-766.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and the absolute.Henry E. Kyburg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The problem of content in embodied memory.Martin Kurthen, Thomas Grunwald, Christoph Helmstaedter & Christian E. Elger - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5):641-642.
    An action-oriented theory of embodied memory is favorable for many reasons, but it will not provide a quick yet clean solution to the grounding problem in the way Glenberg (1997t) envisages. Although structural mapping via analogical representations may be an adequate mechanism of cognitive representation, it will not suffice to explain representation as such.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indeterminiertheit, iterabilität und intentionalität.Martin Kurthen - 1989 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):54-86.
    In his recent paper "Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person" John R. Searle tries to refute Willard V. O. Quine's famous "indeterminacy of translation thesis" by arguing that this thesis is in fact a reductio ad absurdum of Quine's own "linguistic behaviorism". Searle accuses Quine of being "antimentalistic" and suggests that the "absurdity" of Quine's thesis might be avoided if a full-fledged "intentionality" were tolerated in the debate on meaning. - This anti-Quinean approach in some respects reminds of the "improbable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indeterminiertheit, Iterabilität und Intentionalität.Martin Kurthen - 1989 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):54-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Searle conscious?John C. Kulli - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):614-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial intelligence, culture and education.Sergey B. Kulikov & Anastasiya V. Shirokova - 2021 - AI and Society 36 (1):305-318.
    Sequential transformative design of research :224–235, 2015; Groleau et al. in J Mental Health 16:731–741, 2007; Robson and McCartan in Real world research: a resource for users of social research methods in applied settings, Wiley, Chichester, 2016) allows testing a group of theoretical assumptions about the connections of artificial intelligence with culture and education. In the course of research, semiotics ensures the description of self-organizing systems of cultural signs and symbols in terms of artificial intelligence as a special set of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Medium AI and experimental science.Andre Kukla - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (4):493-5012.
    It has been claimed that a great deal of AI research is an attempt to discover the empirical laws describing a new type of entity in the world—the artificial computing system. I call this enterprise 'medium AI', since it is in some respects stronger than Searle's 'weak AI', and in other respects weaker than 'strong AI'. Bruce Buchanan, among others, conceives of medium AI as an empirical science entirely on a par with psychology or chemistry. I argue that medium AI (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connecting Information with Scientific Method: Darwin’s Significance for Epistemology. [REVIEW]Matthias Kuhle & Sabine Kuhle - 2010 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 41 (2):333 - 357.
    Theories of epistemology make reference—via the perspective of an observer—to the structure of information transfer, which generates reality, of which the observer himself forms a part. It can be shown that any epistemological approach which implies the participation of tautological structural elements in the information transfer necessarily leads to an antinomy. Nevertheless, since the time of Aristotle the paradigm of mathematics—and thus tautological structure—has always been a hidden ingredient in the various concepts of knowledge acquisition or general theories of information (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computing machines can't be intelligent (...And Turing said so).Peter Kugel - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (4):563-579.
    According to the conventional wisdom, Turing said that computing machines can be intelligent. I don't believe it. I think that what Turing really said was that computing machines –- computers limited to computing –- can only fake intelligence. If we want computers to become genuinelyintelligent, we will have to give them enough “initiative” to do more than compute. In this paper, I want to try to develop this idea. I want to explain how giving computers more ``initiative'' can allow them (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Formal operations and simulated thought.John-Michael Kuczynski - 2006 - Philosophical Explorations 9 (2):221-234.
    A series of representations must be semantics-driven if the members of that series are to combine into a single thought: where semantics is not operative, there is at most a series of disjoint representations that add up to nothing true or false, and therefore do not constitute a thought at all. A consequence is that there is necessarily a gulf between simulating thought, on the one hand, and actually thinking, on the other. A related point is that a popular doctrine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How connectionist models learn: The course of learning in connectionist networks.John K. Kruschke - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):498-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From genes to culture: The missing links.Joseph K. Kovach - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):15-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the descriptive terminology of the information transfer between organisms.Jolanta Koszteyn & Piotr Lenartowicz - 1970 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 4 (1):165-206.
    Information transfer implies two independent beings and two distinct, although closely tied levels of reality. In other words the „information transfer" is a multi-layer reality. The investigation of the „causal" mechanisms presupposes a proper description of the phenomenal effects. It is the phenomenal sphere of the directly observable events which provokes - in our mind - the questions driving the effort to explore the „mechanisms". It is absolutely crucial, therefore, to approach the process of description with the sufficiently unbiased means. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the descriptive terminology of the information transfer between organisms.Jolanta Koszteyn & Piotr Lenartowicz - 1970 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 4 (1):165-201.
    Information transfer implies two independent beings and two distinct, although closely tied levels of reality. In other words the „information transfer" is a multi-layer reality. The investigation of the „causal" mechanisms presupposes a proper description of the phenomenal effects. It is the phenomenal sphere of the directly observable events which provokes - in our mind - the questions driving the effort to explore the „mechanisms". It is absolutely crucial, therefore, to approach the process of description with the sufficiently unbiased means. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Justified Group Belief, Group Knowledge and Being in a Position to Know.Jakob Koscholke - 2020 - Episteme 20 (1):1-8.
    Jennifer Lackey has recently presented a new and lucid analysis of the notion ofjustified group belief, i.e. a set of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for a group to justifiedly believe some proposition. In this paper, however, I argue that theanalysansshe proposes is too narrow: one of the conditions she takes to be necessary for justified group belief is not necessary. To substantiate this claim, I present a potential counterexample to Lackey's analysis where a group knows and thus justifiedly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rosalind W. Picard, affective computing.Carolyn Korsmeyer - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (3):443-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's doctrine of education and the problem of artificial intelligence.Leonid Kornilaev - 2021 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 55 (6):1072-1080.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ontological and epistemological superiority of hylomorphism.Robert C. Koons - 2017 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 3):885-903.
    Materialism—the view that all of reality is wholly determined by the very, very small—and extreme nominalism—the view that properties, kinds, and qualities do not really exist—have been the dominant view in analytic philosophy for the last 100 years or so. Both views, however, have failed to provide adequate accounts for the possibility of intentionality and of knowledge. We must therefore look to alternatives. One well-tested alternative, the hylomorphism of Aristotle and the medieval scholastics, was rejected without being refuted and so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the generality of PARRY, Colby's paranoia model.Manfred Kochen - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):540-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-attributions help constitute mental types.Bernard W. Kobes - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):54-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Another opening in the explanatory gap.John P. Kline - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (2):185-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Religious naturalism or theological humanism?David E. Klemm - 2007 - Zygon 42 (2):357-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Physical scale effects and philosophical thought experiments.Robert Klee - 2008 - Metaphilosophy 39 (1):89–104.
    The scales across which physical properties exist are vast and subtle in their effects on particular systems placed locally on such scales. For example, human experiential access is restricted only to partial segments of the mass density, size, and temperature scales of the universe. I argue that philosophers must learn to appreciate better the effects of physical scales. Specifically, thought experiments in philosophy should be more sensitive to physical scale effects, because the conclusion of a thought experiment may be undermined (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness and quantum mechanics: Opting from alternatives.David E. Klemm & William H. Klink - 2008 - Zygon 43 (2):307-327.
    We present a model of a fundamental property of consciousness as the capacity of a system to opt among presented alternatives. Any system possessing this capacity is "conscious" in some degree, whether or not it has the higher capacity of reflecting on its opting. We argue that quantum systems, composed of microphysical particles, as studied by quantum mechanics, possess this quality in a protomental form. That is, such particles display the capacity to opt among alternatives, even though they lack the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Meaning of Embodiment.Julian Kiverstein - 2012 - Topics in Cognitive Science 4 (4):740-758.
    There is substantial disagreement among philosophers of embodied cognitive science about the meaning of embodiment. In what follows, I describe three different views that can be found in the current literature. I show how this debate centers around the question of whether the science of embodied cognition can retain the computer theory of mind. One view, which I will label body functionalism, takes the body to play the functional role of linking external resources for problem solving with internal biological machinery. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The devil, the details, and Dr. Dennett.Patricia Kitcher & Philip Kitcher - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Marr’s Computational Theory of Vision.Patricia Kitcher - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (March):1-24.
    David Marr's theory of vision has been widely cited by philosophers and psychologists. I have three projects in this paper. First, I try to offer a perspicuous characterization of Marr's theory. Next, I consider the implications of Marr's work for some currently popular philosophies of psychology, specifically, the "hegemony of neurophysiology view", the theories of Jerry Fodor, Daniel Dennett, and Stephen Stich, and the view that perception is permeated by belief. In the last section, I consider what the phenomenon of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Chronic sensory pain.Patricia Kitcher - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):63-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Competence models are causal.David Kirsh - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Septohippocampal comparator: Consciousness generator or attention feedback loop?Marcel Kinsbourne - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):687-688.
    As Gray insists, his comparator model proposes a brute correlation only – of consciousness with septohippocampal output. I suggest that the comparator straddles a feedback loop that boosts the activation ofnovelrepresentations, thus helping them feature in present or recollected experience. Such a role in organizing conscious contents would transcend correlation and help explain how consciousness emerges from brain function.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reduction, explanation, and individualism.Harold Kincaid - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (4):492-513.
    This paper contributes to the recently renewed debate over methodological individualism (MI) by carefully sorting out various individualist claims and by making use of recent work on reduction and explanation outside the social sciences. My major focus is on individualist claims about reduction and explanation. I argue that reductionist versions of MI fail for much the same reasons that mental predicates cannot be reduced to physical predicates and that attempts to establish reducibility by weakening the requirements for reduction also fail. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Common sense and adult theory of communication.Boaz Keysar - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):54-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Commentary: Robots As Intentional Agents: Using Neuroscientific Methods to Make Robots Appear More Social.Viktor Kewenig, Yuefang Zhou & Martin H. Fischer - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Legal Person- or Agenthood of Artificial Intelligence Technologies.Tanel Kerikmäe, Peeter Müürsepp, Henri Mart Pihl, Ondrej Ondrej Hamuľák & Hovsep Kocharyan - 2020 - Acta Baltica Historiae Et Philosophiae Scientiarum 8 (2):73-92.
    Artificial intelligence is developing rapidly. There are technologies available that fulfil several tasks better than humans can and even behave like humans to some extent. Thus, the situation prompts the question whether AI should be granted legal person- and/or agenthood? There have been similar situations in history where the legal status of slaves or indigenous peoples was discussed. Still, in those historical questions, the subjects under study were always natural persons, i.e., they were living beings belonging to the species Homo (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Mechanistic Account of Wide Computationalism.Luke Kersten - 2017 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 8 (3):501-517.
    The assumption that psychological states and processes are computational in character pervades much of cognitive science, what many call the computational theory of mind. In addition to occupying a central place in cognitive science, the computational theory of mind has also had a second life supporting “individualism”, the view that psychological states should be taxonomized so as to supervene only on the intrinsic, physical properties of individuals. One response to individualism has been to raise the prospect of “wide computational systems”, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Parallelism and patterns of thought.R. W. Kentridge - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):670-671.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Motor control: Which themes do we orchestrate?J. A. S. Kelso & E. L. Saltzman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):554-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Information, causality, and intentionality.David Kelley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):147-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial life for philosophers.Brian L. Keeley - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (2):251 – 260.
    Artificial life (ALife) is the attempt to create artificial instances of life in a variety of media, but primarily within the digital computer. As such, the field brings together computationally-minded biologists and biologically-minded computer scientists. I argue that this new field is filled with interesting philosophical issues. However, there is a dearth of philosophers actively conducting research in this area. I discuss two books on the new field: Margaret A. Boden's The philosophy of artificial life and Christopher G. Langton's Artificial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Systems analysis in the study of the motor-control system: Control theory alone is insufficient.R. E. Kearney & I. W. Hunter - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant and the simulation hypothesis.Gagan Deep Kaur - 2015 - AI and Society 30 (2):183-192.
    Computational imagination (CI) conceives imagination as an agent’s simulated sensorimotor interaction with the environment in the absence of sensory feedback, predicting consequences based on this interaction (Marques and Holland in Neurocomputing 72:743–759, 2009). Its bedrock is the simulation hypothesis whereby imagination resembles seeing or doing something in reality as both involve similar neural structures in the brain (Hesslow in Trends Cogn Sci 6(6):242–247, 2002). This paper raises two-forked doubts: (1) neural-level equivalence is escalated to make phenomenological equivalence. Even at an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The gradual evolution of enhanced control by plans: A view from below.Leonard D. Katz - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):764-765.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Question of Consciousness: to Quantum Mechanics for the Answers.Ivan A. Karpenko - 2014 - Studia Humana 3 (3):16-28.
    The article presents the possible role of consciousness in quantum-mechanical description of physical reality. The widely spread interpretations of quantum phenomena are considered as indicating the apparent connection between conscious processes and the properties of the microcosm. The reasons for discrepancies between the results of observations of the microcosm and macrocosm and the potential association of consciousness with these reasons are closely investigated. The mentioned connection is meant to be interpreted in the sense that the probable requirement for a complete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How would you know if you synthesized a thinking thing?Michael Kary & Martin Mahner - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (1):61-86.
    We confront the following popular views: that mind or life are algorithms; that thinking, or more generally any process other than computation, is computation; that anything other than a working brain can have thoughts; that anything other than a biological organism can be alive; that form and function are independent of matter; that sufficiently accurate simulations are just as genuine as the real things they imitate; and that the Turing test is either a necessary or sufficient or scientific procedure for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Human achievement and artificial intelligence.Brett Karlan - 2023 - Ethics and Information Technology 25 (3):1-12.
    In domains as disparate as playing Go and predicting the structure of proteins, artificial intelligence (AI) technologies have begun to perform at levels beyond which any humans can achieve. Does this fact represent something lamentable? Does superhuman AI performance somehow undermine the value of human achievements in these areas? Go grandmaster Lee Sedol suggested as much when he announced his retirement from professional Go, blaming the advances of Go-playing programs like AlphaGo for sapping his will to play the game at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The structure of semantic norms.Jeffrey Kaplan - 2023 - Analytic Philosophy 64 (4):373-391.
    The normativity of meaning—introduced by Kripke in 1982, and the subject of active debate since the early 1990s—has been exclusively understood in terms of duty-imposing norms. But there are norms of another type, well-known within the philosophy of law: authority-conferring norms. Philosophers thinking and writing about the normativity of meaning—normativists, anti-normativists, and even Kripke himself—seem to have failed to consider the possibility that semantic norms are authority-conferring. I argue that semantic norms should be understood as having an authority-conferring structure, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to demarcate the boundaries of cognition.David Michael Kaplan - 2012 - Biology and Philosophy 27 (4):545-570.
    Advocates of extended cognition argue that the boundaries of cognition span brain, body, and environment. Critics maintain that cognitive processes are confined to a boundary centered on the individual. All participants to this debate require a criterion for distinguishing what is internal to cognition from what is external. Yet none of the available proposals are completely successful. I offer a new account, the mutual manipulability account, according to which cognitive boundaries are determined by relationships of mutual manipulability between the properties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations