Switch to: References

Citations of:

On signs

In Jonathan Barnes & J. Brunschwig (eds.), Science and Speculation: Studies in Hellenistic Theory and Practice. Paris: Cambridge University Press. pp. 239--272 (1982)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Abū Bakr al-Rāzī et le signe: Fragment retrouvé d'un traité logique perdu.Pauline Koetschet - 2017 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 27 (1):75-114.
    This article argues that a fragment from a lost treatise by Abū Bakr al-Rāzī (d. 925) is preserved in the Book on Morphology Kitāb al-Taṣrīf) by Ps-Ǧābir ibn Ḥayyān. Paul Kraus reached the conclusion that the collection to which this book belongs was written between the end of the ninth and the beginning of the tenth century AD. This fragment represents the first attempt – to our knowledge – to analyze the logical structure of sign-based inference in Arabic, which is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Štyri antické argumenty o budúcich nahodnostiach (Four Ancient Arguments on Future Contingencies).Vladimir Marko - 2017 - Bratislava, Slovakia: Univerzita Komenského.
    Essays on Aristotle's Sea-Battle, Lazy Argument, Argument Reaper, Diodorus' Master Argument -/- The book is devoted to the ancient logical theories, reconstruction of their semantic proprieties and possibilities of their interpretation by modern logical tools. The Ancient arguments are frequently misunderstood in modern interpretations since authors usually have tendency to ignore their historical proprieties and theoretical background what usually leads to a quite inappropriate picture of the argument’s original form and mission. Author’s primary intention was to draw attention to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vreme, objasnjenje, modalnost (Time, Explanation, Modality).Vladimir Marko - 2004 - Novi Sad, Serbia: Futura.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Demetrius of Laconia and the debate between the Stoics and the Epicureans on the nature of parental love.Sean McConnell - 2017 - Classical Quarterly 67 (1):149-162.
    Epicurus denies that human beings have natural parental love for their children, and his account of the development of justice and human political community does not involve any natural affinity between human beings in general but rather a form of social contract. The Stoics to the contrary assert that parental love is natural; and, moreover, they maintain that natural parental love is the first principle of social οἰκείωσις, which provides the basis for the naturalness of justice and human political community. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epicurus on Truth and Falsehood.Alexander Bown - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (4):463–503.
    Sextus Empiricus ascribes to Epicurus a curious account of truth and falsehood, according to which these characteristics belong to things in the world about which one speaks, not to what one says about them. I propose an interpretation that takes this account seriously and explains the connection between truth and existence that the Epicureans also seem to recognise. I then examine a second Epicurean account of truth and falsehood and show how it is related to the first.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philodemus De signis: An important ancient semiotic debate.Giovanni Manetti - 2002 - Semiotica 2002 (138).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Stoicism bibliography.Ronald H. Epp - 1984 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1):125-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skeptic Semiotics.David Glidden - 1983 - Phronesis 28 (3):213-255.
    This article presents a detailed exploration of what Sextus and Pyrrhonists regarded as mnemonic signs, where one experience reminds us of another, such as seeing smoke reminds us of a fire that is not yet evident to our present observations. For the skeptic the use of mnemonic signs obviates the need for reasoned, theoretical interpretations or elaborated belief formation. It allows the skeptic or the theory-free physician, for that matter, to live a life or practice symptomatic medicine without the need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Chrysippus and the destruction of propositions: a defence of the standard interpretation.Michael B. Papazian - 2001 - History and Philosophy of Logic 22 (1):1-12.
    One of the most intriguing claims of Stoic logic is Chrysippus's denial of the modal principle that the impossible does not follow from the possible. Chrysippus's argument against this principle involves the idea that some propositions are ?destroyed? or ?perish?. According to the standard interpretation of Chrysippus's argument, propositions cease to exist when they are destroyed. Ide has presented an alternative interpretation according to which destroyed propositions persist after destruction and are false. I argue that Ide's alternative interpretation as well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Chrysippus’s response to Diodorus’s master argument.Harry A. Ide - 1992 - History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (2):133-148.
    Chrysippus claims that some propositions perish. including some true conditionals whose consequent is impossible and antecedent is possible, to which he appeals against Diodorus?s Master Argument. On the standard interpretation. perished propositions lack truth values. and these conditionals are true at the same time as their antecedents arc possible and consequents impossible. But perished propositions are false, and Chrysippus?s conditionals are true when their antecedent and consequent arc possible, and false when their antecedent is possible and consequent impossible. The claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Colloquium 11.Phillip Mitsis - 1990 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1):447-454.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark