Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Prodikos, 'Meteorosophists' and the 'Tantalos' Paradigm.C. W. Willink - 1983 - Classical Quarterly 33 (01):25-.
    Three famous sophists are referred to together in the Apology of Sokrates as still practising their enviably lucrative itinerant profession in 399 b.c. : Gorgias of Leontinoi, Prodikos of Keos and Hippias of Elis. The last of these was the least well known to the Athenian demos, having practised mainly in I Dorian cities. There is no extant reference to him in Old Comedy, but we can assume that he was sufficiently famous – especially for his fees – to justify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Divine Madness in Plato’s Phaedrus.Matthew Shelton - 2024 - Apeiron 57 (2):245-264.
    Critics often suggest that Socrates’ portrait of the philosopher’s inspired madness in his second speech in Plato’s Phaedrus is incompatible with the other types of divine madness outlined in the same speech, namely poetic, prophetic, and purificatory madness. This incompatibility is frequently taken to show that Socrates’ characterisation of philosophers as mad is disingenuous or misleading in some way. While philosophical madness and the other types of divine madness are distinguished by the non-philosophical crowd’s different interpretations of them, I aim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rhythm and Refrain: In Between Philosophy and Arts (2016).Jurate Baranova (ed.) - 2016 - Vilnius: Lithuanian University of educational sciences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Returning to the Heavens: Plato’s Socrates on Anaxagoras and Natural Philosophy.Samuel Ortencio Flores - 2020 - Apeiron 53 (2):123-146.
    Readers of Plato since antiquity have generally taken Socrates’ intellectual autobiography in the Phaedo as a signal of his turn away from the study of natural philosophy. They have turned instead to characters such as Timaeus for evidence of Plato’s pursuit of physics. This article argues that Plato’s Socrates himself developed a philosophy of nature in his criticism of Anaxagoras and his subsequent philosophic pursuits. Socrates’ autobiography places the study of nature in a foundational position within the development of his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mintis kaip tarpinė teritorija tarp žodžio ir vaizdo.Jūratė Baranova - 2015 - Žmogus ir Žodis 17 (4).
    Šiame straipsnyje siekiama atsakyti į klausimą, kas galėtų susieti filosofiją ir vizualiuosius bei žodinius menus. Ar įmanoma ir jei taip, tai kaip įmanoma reflektuoti visus menus kaip vieno kūrybinio įvykio momentus? Siekiant atsakyti į šį klausimą, pirma, aptariamas logikos ir kūrybiškumo susikertant menui ir filosofijai susidūrimas, antra – žodžio ir vaizdo nebendramatiškumas, surastas / išrastas belgų siurrealisto René Magritte’o ir reflektuotas Michelio Foucault. Čia sugrįžtama prie klasikinio F. Niezsche’s disputo su Sokratu apie logikos ir kūrybiškumo priešpriešą ir siekiama atsakyti į (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Prodikos, ‘Meteorosophists’ and the ‘Tantalos’ Paradigm.C. W. Willink - 1983 - Classical Quarterly 33 (1):25-33.
    Three famous sophists are referred to together in theApology of Sokratesas still practising their enviably lucrative itinerant profession in 399b.c.(not, by implication, I in Athens): Gorgias of Leontinoi, Prodikos of Keos and Hippias of Elis. The last of these was the least well known to the Atheniandemos, having practised mainly in I Dorian cities. There is no extant reference to him in Old Comedy, but we can assume that he was sufficiently famous – especially for his fees (possibly the highest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Threshold of Rhetoric.Jonathan Pratt - 2015 - Classical Antiquity 34 (1):163-182.
    The Helen of Gorgias is designed to provoke the aspiring speaker to consider his relationship with society as a whole. The speech's extreme claims regarding the power of logos reflect simplistic ideas about speaker-audience relations current among Gorgias' target audience, ideas reflected in an interpretive stance towards model speeches that privileges method over truth. The Helen pretends to encourage this conception of logos and interpretive stance in order to expose the intense desire and naïve credulity that drive a coolly technical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Clitophon and Socrates in the Platonic Clitophon.Christopher Moore - 2012 - Ancient Philosophy 32 (2):257-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Embodying the Tragic Father(s): Autobiography and Intertextuality in Aristophanes.Mario Telò - 2010 - Classical Antiquity 29 (2):278-326.
    This paper examines the role of the generation gap in Aristophanes' construction of his persona throughout Wasps, Clouds, and Peace. It contends that in Wasps and Clouds Aristophanes defines the relationship with his audience and his rivals by presenting himself as the figure of a paternal son. The same stance shapes the comic poet's generic self-positioning in the initial scene of Peace, where the parody of Euripides' Aeolus and Bellerophon evinces a corrective attitude in relation not only to the troubled (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristophanes' Adôniazousai.L. Reitzammer - 2008 - Classical Antiquity 27 (2):282-333.
    A scholiast's note on Lysistrata mentions that there was an alternative title to the play: Adôniazousai. A close reading of the play with this title in mind reveals that Lysistrata and her allies metaphorically hold an Adonis festival atop the Acropolis. The Adonia, a festival that is typically regarded as “marginal” and “private” by modern scholars, thus becomes symbolically central and public as the sex-strike held by the women halts the Peloponnesian war. The public space of the Acropolis becomes, notionally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Commentary on Inwood.Margaret Graver - 1999 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):44-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • To Sit in Solemn Silence? Thronosis in Ritual, Myth, and Iconography.Radcliffe G. Edmonds - 2006 - American Journal of Philology 127 (3):347-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truth, Narration, and Interpretation in Lucian's Verae Historiae.Calum Alasdair Maciver - 2016 - American Journal of Philology 137 (2):219-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Herodotus and the Map of Aristagoras.David Branscome - 2010 - Classical Antiquity 29 (1):1-44.
    Herodotus uses the encounter between the Milesian tyrant Aristagoras and the Spartan king Cleomenes to further his authorial self-presentation. He contrasts his own aims and methods as an inquirer with those of Aristagoras, who becomes a “rival” inquirer for Herodotus in this passage. Seeking military aid from Cleomenes for the Ionian Revolt, Aristagoras points to his bronze map of the world and gives an ethnographical and geographical account of the peoples and land of Asia, from Ionia to Susa. Aristagoras accordingly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark