Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Generic variations of models of T.Andreas Baudisch - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1025-1038.
    Let T be a model-complete theory that eliminates the quantifier $\exists^\infty x$ . For T we construct a theory T+ such that any element in a model of T+ determines a model of T. We show that T+ has a model companion T1. We can iterate the construction. The produced theories are investigated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Local homogeneity.Bektur Baizhanov & John T. Baldwin - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (4):1243-1260.
    We study the expansion of stable structures by adding predicates for arbitrary subsets. Generalizing work of Poizat-Bouscaren on the one hand and Baldwin-Benedikt-Casanovas-Ziegler on the other we provide a sufficient condition for such an expansion to be stable. This generalization weakens the original definitions in two ways: dealing with arbitrary subsets rather than just submodels and removing the ‘small' or ‘belles paires' hypothesis. We use this generalization to characterize in terms of pairs, the ‘triviality' of the geometry on a strongly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Subsets of superstable structures are weakly benign.Bektur Baizhanov, John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (1):142-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Expansion of a model of a weakly o-minimal theory by a family of unary predicates.Bektur Sembiuly Baizhanov - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1382-1414.
    A subsetA⊆Mof a totally ordered structureMis said to beconvex, if for anya, b∈A: [a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the number of nonisomorphic models of an infinitary theory which has the infinitary order property. Part A.Rami Grossberg & Saharon Shelah - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):302-322.
    Let κ and λ be infinite cardinals such that κ ≤ λ (we have new information for the case when $\kappa ). Let T be a theory in L κ +, ω of cardinality at most κ, let φ(x̄, ȳ) ∈ L λ +, ω . Now define $\mu^\ast_\varphi (\lambda, T) = \operatorname{Min} \{\mu^\ast:$ If T satisfies $(\forall\mu \kappa)(\exists M_\chi \models T)(\exists \{a_i: i Our main concept in this paper is $\mu^\ast_\varphi (\lambda, \kappa) = \operatorname{Sup}\{\mu^\ast(\lambda, T): T$ is a theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Generalizations of Deissler's Minimality Rank.T. G. Kucera - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):269-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem for infinitary theories which have the unsuperstability property.Rami Grossberg - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):231-242.
    We present a downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem which transfers downward formulas from L ∞,ω to L κ +, ω . The simplest instance is: Theorem 1. Let $\lambda > \kappa$ be infinite cardinals, and let L be a similarity type of cardinality κ at most. For every L-structure M of cardinality λ and every $X \subseteq M$ there exists a model $N \prec M$ containing the set X of power |X| · κ such that for every pair of finite sequences a, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Completeness and categoricity (in power): Formalization without foundationalism.John T. Baldwin - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):39-79.
    We propose a criterion to regard a property of a theory (in first or second order logic) as virtuous: the property must have significant mathematical consequences for the theory (or its models). We then rehearse results of Ajtai, Marek, Magidor, H. Friedman and Solovay to argue that for second order logic, ‘categoricity’ has little virtue. For first order logic, categoricity is trivial; but ‘categoricity in power’ has enormous structural consequences for any of the theories satisfying it. The stability hierarchy extends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Craig Interpolation Theorem in abstract model theory.Jouko Väänänen - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):401-420.
    The Craig Interpolation Theorem is intimately connected with the emergence of abstract logic and continues to be the driving force of the field. I will argue in this paper that the interpolation property is an important litmus test in abstract model theory for identifying “natural,” robust extensions of first order logic. My argument is supported by the observation that logics which satisfy the interpolation property usually also satisfy a Lindström type maximality theorem. Admittedly, the range of such logics is small.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Theories without the tree property of the second kind.Artem Chernikov - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):695-723.
    We initiate a systematic study of the class of theories without the tree property of the second kind — NTP2. Most importantly, we show: the burden is “sub-multiplicative” in arbitrary theories ; NTP2 is equivalent to the generalized Kimʼs lemma and to the boundedness of ist-weight; the dp-rank of a type in an arbitrary theory is witnessed by mutually indiscernible sequences of realizations of the type, after adding some parameters — so the dp-rank of a 1-type in any theory is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Non-forking frames in abstract elementary classes.Adi Jarden & Saharon Shelah - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):135-191.
    The stability theory of first order theories was initiated by Saharon Shelah in 1969. The classification of abstract elementary classes was initiated by Shelah, too. In several papers, he introduced non-forking relations. Later, Shelah [17, II] introduced the good non-forking frame, an axiomatization of the non-forking notion.We improve results of Shelah on good non-forking frames, mainly by weakening the stability hypothesis in several important theorems, replacing it by the almost λ-stability hypothesis: The number of types over a model of cardinality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Classification theory for abelian groups with an endomorphism.Annalisa Marcja, Mike Prest & Carlo Toffalori - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (2):95-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thorn-forking as local forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):21-38.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On theories having a finite number of nonisomorphic countable models.Akito Tsuboi - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):806-808.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Independence results.Saharon Shelah - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):563-573.
    We prove independence results concerning the number of nonisomorphic models (using the S-chain condition and S-properness) and the consistency of "ZCF + 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 2 + there is a universal linear order of power ℵ 1 ". Most of these results were announced in [Sh 4], [Sh 5]. In subsequent papers we shall prove an analog f MA for forcing which does not destroy stationary subsets of ω 1 , investigate D-properness for various filters and prove the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Théories instables.Bruno Poizat - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (3):513-522.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • PAS d'imaginaires dans l'infini!Anand Pillay & Bruno Poizat - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (2):400-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Closed sets and chain conditions in stable theories.Anand Pillay & Gabriel Srour - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1350-1362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dimension theory and homogeneity for elementary extensions of a model.Anand Pillay - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):147-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Théories d'arbres.Michel Parigot - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):841-853.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The baire category theorem and cardinals of countable cofinality.Arnold W. Miller - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):275-288.
    Let κ B be the least cardinal for which the Baire category theorem fails for the real line R. Thus κ B is the least κ such that the real line can be covered by κ many nowhere dense sets. It is shown that κ B cannot have countable cofinality. On the other hand it is consistent that the corresponding cardinal for 2 ω 1 be ℵ ω . Similar questions are considered for the ideal of measure zero sets, other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Cantor-bendixson spectra containing (1,1). II.Annalisa Marcja & Carlo Toffalori - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):611-618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Uncountable theories that are categorical in a higher power.Michael Chris Laskowski - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):512-530.
    In this paper we prove three theorems about first-order theories that are categorical in a higher power. The first theorem asserts that such a theory either is totally categorical or there exist prime and minimal models over arbitrary base sets. The second theorem shows that such theories have a natural notion of dimension that determines the models of the theory up to isomorphism. From this we conclude that $I(T, \aleph_\alpha) = \aleph_0 +|\alpha|$ where ℵ α = the number of formulas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The number of one-generated cylindric set algebras of dimension greater than two.Jean A. Larson - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):59-71.
    S. Ulam asked about the number of nonisomorphic projective algebras with k generators. This paper answers his question for projective algebras of finite dimension at least three and shows that there are the maximum possible number, continuum many, of nonisomorphic one-generated structures of finite dimension n, where n is at least three, of the following kinds: projective set algebras, projective algebras, diagonal-free cylindric set algebras, diagonal-free cylindric algebras, cylindric set algebras, and cylindric algebras. The results of this paper extend earlier (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nonexistence of universal orders in many cardinals.Menachem Kojman & Saharon Shelah - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):875-891.
    Our theme is that not every interesting question in set theory is independent of ZFC. We give an example of a first order theory T with countable D(T) which cannot have a universal model at ℵ1 without CH; we prove in ZFC a covering theorem from the hypothesis of the existence of a universal model for some theory; and we prove--again in ZFC--that for a large class of cardinals there is no universal linear order (e.g. in every regular $\aleph_1 < (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • From stability to simplicity.Byunghan Kim & Anand Pillay - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (1):17-36.
    §1. Introduction. In this report we wish to describe recent work on a class of first order theories first introduced by Shelah in [32], the simple theories. Major progress was made in the first author's doctoral thesis [17]. We will give a survey of this, as well as further works by the authors and others.The class of simple theories includes stable theories, but also many more, such as the theory of the random graph. Moreover, many of the theories of particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Model companions of theories with an automorphism.Hirotaka Kikyo - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1215-1222.
    For a theory T in L, T σ is the theory of the models of T with an automorphism σ. If T is an unstable model complete theory without the independence property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is an unstable model complete theory and T σ has the amalgamation property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is model complete and has the fcp, then T σ has no model completion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On regular reduced products.Juliette Kennedy & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1169-1177.
    Assume $\langle \aleph_0, \aleph_1 \rangle \rightarrow \langle \lambda, \lambda^+ \rangle$ . Assume M is a model of a first order theory T of cardinality at most λ+ in a language L(T) of cardinality $\leq \lambda$ . Let N be a model with the same language. Let Δ be a set of first order formulas in L(T) and let D be a regular filter on λ. Then M is $\Delta-embeddable$ into the reduced power $N^\lambda/D$ , provided that every $\Delta-existential$ formula true (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Remarks on weak notions of saturation in models of peano arithmetic.Matt Kaufmann & James H. Schmerl - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):129-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Definability in functional analysis.José Iovino - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):493-505.
    The role played by real-valued functions in functional analysis is fundamental. One often considers metrics, or seminorms, or linear functionals, to mention some important examples. We introduce the notion of definable real-valued function in functional analysis: a real-valued function f defined on a structure of functional analysis is definable if it can be "approximated" by formulas which do not involve f. We characterize definability of real-valued functions in terms of a purely topological condition which does not involve logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A version of o-minimality for the p-adics.Deirdre Haskell & Dugald Macpherson - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (4):1075-1092.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The classification of excellent classes.R. Grossberg & B. Hart - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1359-1381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On chains of relatively saturated submodels of a model without the order property.Rami Grossberg - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):124-128.
    Let M be a given model with similarity type L = L(M), and let L' be any fragment of L |L(M)| +, ω of cardinality |L(M)|. We call $N \prec M L'$ -relatively saturated $\operatorname{iff}$ for every $B \subseteq N$ of cardinality less than | N | every L'-type over B which is realized in M is realized in M is realized in N. We discuss the existence of such submodels. The following are corollaries of the existence theorems. (1) If (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Quasi-o-minimal structures.Oleg Belegradek, Ya'acov Peterzil & Frank Wagner - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1115-1132.
    A structure (M, $ ,...) is called quasi-o-minimal if in any structure elementarily equivalent to it the definable subsets are exactly the Boolean combinations of 0-definable subsets and intervals. We give a series of natural examples of quasi-o-minimal structures which are not o-minimal; one of them is the ordered group of integers. We develop a technique to investigate quasi-o-minimality and use it to study quasi-o-minimal ordered groups (possibly with extra structure). Main results: any quasi-o-minimal ordered group is abelian; any quasi-o-minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The spectrum of resplendency.John T. Baldwin - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):626-636.
    Let T be a complete countable first order theory and λ an uncountable cardinal. Theorem 1. If T is not superstable, T has 2 λ resplendent models of power λ. Theorem 2. If T is strictly superstable, then T has at least $\min(2^\lambda,\beth_2)$ resplendent models of power λ. Theorem 3. If T is not superstable or is small and strictly superstable, then every resplendent homogeneous model of T is saturated. Theorem 4 (with Knight). For each μ ∈ ω ∪ {ω, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • DOP and FCP in generic structures.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (2):427-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Diverse classes.John T. Baldwin - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):875-893.
    Let $\mathbf{I}(\mu,K)$ denote the number of nonisomorphic models of power $\mu$ and $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K)$ the number of nonmutually embeddable models. We define in this paper the notion of a diverse class and use it to prove a number of results. The major result is Theorem B: For any diverse class $K$ and $\mu$ greater than the cardinality of the language of $K$, $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K) \geq \min(2^\mu,\beth_2).$ From it we deduce both an old result of Shelah, Theorem C: If $T$ is countable and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Expansion of a model of a weakly o-minimal theory by a family of unary predicates.Bektur Sembiuly Baizhanov - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1382-1414.
    A subset A $\subseteq$ M of a totally ordered structure M is said to be convex, if for any a, b $\in A: [a . A complete theory of first order is weakly o-minimal (M. Dickmann [D]) if any model M is totally ordered by some $\emptyset$ -definable formula and any subset of M which is definable with parameters from M is a finite union of convex sets. We prove here that for any model M of a weakly o-minimal theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Rich models.Michael H. Albert & Rami P. Grossberg - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1292-1298.
    We define a rich model to be one which contains a proper elementary substructure isomorphic to itself. Existence, nonstructure, and categoricity theorems for rich models are proved. A theory T which has fewer than $\min(2^\lambda,\beth_2)$ rich models of cardinality $\lambda(\lambda > |T|)$ is totally transcendental. We show that a countable theory with a unique rich model in some uncountable cardinal is categorical in ℵ 1 and also has a unique countable rich model. We also consider a stronger notion of richness, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A New Perspective on Semi-Retractions and the Ramsey Property.Dana Bartošová & Lynn Scow - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-35.
    We investigate the notion of a semi-retraction between two first-order structures (in typically different signatures) that was introduced by the second author as a link between the Ramsey property and generalized indiscernible sequences. We look at semi-retractions through a new lens establishing transfers of the Ramsey property and finite Ramsey degrees under quite general conditions that are optimal as demonstrated by counterexamples. Finally, we compare semi-retractions to the category theoretic notion of a pre-adjunction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dividing Lines Between Positive Theories.Anna Dmitrieva, Francesco Gallinaro & Mark Kamsma - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-25.
    We generalise the properties $\mathsf {OP}$, $\mathsf {IP}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}$, $\mathsf {TP}_{1}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}_{2}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{1}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{2}$, and $\mathsf {SOP}_{3}$ to positive logic, and prove various implications and equivalences between them. We also provide a characterisation of stability in positive logic in analogy with the one in full first-order logic, both on the level of formulas and on the level of theories. For simple theories there are the classically equivalent definitions of not having $\mathsf {TP}$ and dividing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Undefinability of Multiplication in Presburger Arithmetic with Sets of Powers.Chris Schulz - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-15.
    We begin by proving that any Presburger-definable image of one or more sets of powers has zero natural density. Then, by adapting the proof of a dichotomy result on o-minimal structures by Friedman and Miller, we produce a similar dichotomy for expansions of Presburger arithmetic on the integers. Combining these two results, we obtain that the expansion of the ordered group of integers by any number of sets of powers does not define multiplication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Burden in Henselian valued fields.Pierre Touchard - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (10):103318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An AEC framework for fields with commuting automorphisms.Tapani Hyttinen & Kaisa Kangas - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (7):1001-1032.
    In this paper, we introduce an AEC framework for studying fields with commuting automorphisms. Fields with commuting automorphisms are closely related to difference fields. Some authors define a difference ring (or field) as a ring (or field) together with several commuting endomorphisms, while others only study one endomorphism. Z. Chatzidakis and E. Hrushovski have studied in depth the model theory of ACFA, the model companion of difference fields with one automorphism. Our fields with commuting automorphisms generalize this setting. We have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Axiomatizing AECs and applications.Samson Leung - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (5):103248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Elimination of Imaginaries in Ordered Abelian Groups with Bounded Regular Rank.Mariana Vicaría - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1639-1654.
    In this paper we study elimination of imaginaries in some classes of pure ordered abelian groups. For the class of ordered abelian groups with bounded regular rank (equivalently with finite spines) we obtain weak elimination of imaginaries once we add sorts for the quotient groups $\Gamma /\Delta $ for each definable convex subgroup $\Delta $, and sorts for the quotient groups $\Gamma /(\Delta + \ell \Gamma )$ where $\Delta $ is a definable convex subgroup and $\ell \in \mathbb {N}_{\geq 2}$. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Co-theory of sorted profinite groups for PAC structures.Daniel Max Hoffmann & Junguk Lee - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (3).
    We achieve several results. First, we develop a variant of the theory of absolute Galois groups in the context of many sorted structures. Second, we provide a method for coding absolute Galois groups of structures, so they can be interpreted in some monster model with an additional predicate. Third, we prove the “Weak Independence Theorem” for pseudo-algebraically closed (PAC) substructures of an ambient structure with no finite cover property (nfcp) and the property [Formula: see text]. Fourth, we describe Kim-dividing in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nsop-Like Independence in Aecats.Mark Kamsma - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (2):724-757.
    The classes stable, simple, and NSOP $_1$ in the stability hierarchy for first-order theories can be characterised by the existence of a certain independence relation. For each of them there is a canonicity theorem: there can be at most one nice independence relation. Independence in stable and simple first-order theories must come from forking and dividing (which then coincide), and for NSOP $_1$ theories it must come from Kim-dividing. We generalise this work to the framework of Abstract Elementary Categories (AECats) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hanf number of the first stability cardinal in AECs.Samson Leung - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (2):103201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Turing Degrees and Keisler’s Order.Maryanthe Malliaris & Saharon Shelah - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):331-341.
    There is a Turing functional $\Phi $ taking $A^\prime $ to a theory $T_A$ whose complexity is exactly that of the jump of A, and which has the property that $A \leq _T B$ if and only if $T_A \trianglelefteq T_B$ in Keisler’s order. In fact, by more elaborate means and related theories, we may keep the complexity at the level of A without using the jump.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark