Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Omitting types in logic of metric structures.Ilijas Farah & Menachem Magidor - 2018 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 18 (2):1850006.
    This paper is about omitting types in logic of metric structures introduced by Ben Yaacov, Berenstein, Henson and Usvyatsov. While a complete type is omissible in some model of a countable complete...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reduction of database independence to dividing in atomless Boolean algebras.Tapani Hyttinen & Gianluca Paolini - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):505-518.
    We prove that the form of conditional independence at play in database theory and independence logic is reducible to the first-order dividing calculus in the theory of atomless Boolean algebras. This establishes interesting connections between independence in database theory and stochastic independence. As indeed, in light of the aforementioned reduction and recent work of Ben-Yaacov :957–1012, 2013), the former case of independence can be seen as the discrete version of the latter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Characterizing model-theoretic dividing lines via collapse of generalized indiscernibles.Vincent Guingona, Cameron Donnay Hill & Lynn Scow - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (5):1091-1111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the Strong Martin Conjecture.Masanori Itai - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):862-875.
    We study the following conjecture. Conjecture. Let $T$ be an $\omega$-stable theory with continuum many countable models. Then either i) $T$ has continuum many complete extensions in $L_1$, or ii) some complete extension of $T$ in $L_1$ has continuum many $L_1$-types without parameters. By Shelah's proof of Vaught's conjecture for $\omega$-stable theories, we know that there are seven types of $\omega$-stable theory with continuum many countable models. We show that the conjecture is true for all but one of these seven (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Independence results.Saharon Shelah - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):563-573.
    We prove independence results concerning the number of nonisomorphic models (using the S-chain condition and S-properness) and the consistency of "ZCF + 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 2 + there is a universal linear order of power ℵ 1 ". Most of these results were announced in [Sh 4], [Sh 5]. In subsequent papers we shall prove an analog f MA for forcing which does not destroy stationary subsets of ω 1 , investigate D-properness for various filters and prove the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Categoricity and ranks.Jürgen Saffe - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1379-1392.
    In this paper we investigate the connections between categoricity and ranks. We use stability theory to prove some old and new results.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some remarks on definable equivalence relations in o-minimal structures.Anand Pillay - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):709-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Countable structures of given age.H. D. Macpherson, M. Pouzet & R. E. Woodrow - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):992-1010.
    Let L be a finite relational language. The age of a structure M over L is the set of isomorphism types of finite substructures of M. We classify those ages U for which there are less than 2ω countably infinite pairwise nonisomorphic L-structures of age U.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nonexistence of universal orders in many cardinals.Menachem Kojman & Saharon Shelah - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):875-891.
    Our theme is that not every interesting question in set theory is independent of ZFC. We give an example of a first order theory T with countable D(T) which cannot have a universal model at ℵ1 without CH; we prove in ZFC a covering theorem from the hypothesis of the existence of a universal model for some theory; and we prove--again in ZFC--that for a large class of cardinals there is no universal linear order (e.g. in every regular $\aleph_1 < (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The geometry of weakly minimal types.Steven Buechler - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):1044-1053.
    Let T be superstable. We say a type p is weakly minimal if R(p, L, ∞) = 1. Let $M \models T$ be uncountable and saturated, H = p(M). We say $D \subset H$ is locally modular if for all $X, Y \subset D$ with $X = \operatorname{acl}(X) \cap D, Y = \operatorname{acl}(Y) \cap D$ and $X \cap Y \neq \varnothing$ , dim(X ∪ Y) + dim(X ∩ Y) = dim(X) + dim(Y). Theorem 1. Let p ∈ S(A) be weakly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Lascar strong types in some simple theories.Steven Buechler - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):817-824.
    In this paper a class of simple theories, called the low theories is developed, and the following is proved. Theorem. Let T be a low theory. A set and a, b elements realizing the same strong type over A. Then, a and b realized the same Lascar strong type over A.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Quasi-o-minimal structures.Oleg Belegradek, Ya'acov Peterzil & Frank Wagner - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1115-1132.
    A structure (M, $ ,...) is called quasi-o-minimal if in any structure elementarily equivalent to it the definable subsets are exactly the Boolean combinations of 0-definable subsets and intervals. We give a series of natural examples of quasi-o-minimal structures which are not o-minimal; one of them is the ordered group of integers. We develop a technique to investigate quasi-o-minimality and use it to study quasi-o-minimal ordered groups (possibly with extra structure). Main results: any quasi-o-minimal ordered group is abelian; any quasi-o-minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Partitioning subsets of stable models.Timothy Bays - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1899-1908.
    This paper discusses two combinatorial problems in stability theory. First we prove a partition result for subsets of stable models: for any A and B, we can partition A into |B |<κ(T ) pieces, Ai | i < |B |<κ(T ) , such that for each Ai there is a Bi ⊆ B where |Bi| < κ(T ) and Ai..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A construction of superstable NDOP-NOTOP groups.Andreas Baudisch - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1385-1390.
    The paper continues [1]. Let S be a complete theory of ultraflat (e.g. planar) graphs as introduced in [4]. We show a strong form of NOTOP for S: The union of two models M1 and M2, independent over a common elementary submodel M0, is the primary model over M1 ∪ M2 of S. Then by results of [1] Mekler's construction [6] gives for such a theory S of nice ultraflat graphs a superstable 2-step-nilpotent group of exponent $p (>2)$ with NDOP (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dividing Lines Between Positive Theories.Anna Dmitrieva, Francesco Gallinaro & Mark Kamsma - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-25.
    We generalise the properties$\mathsf {OP}$,$\mathsf {IP}$,k-$\mathsf {TP}$,$\mathsf {TP}_{1}$,k-$\mathsf {TP}_{2}$,$\mathsf {SOP}_{1}$,$\mathsf {SOP}_{2}$, and$\mathsf {SOP}_{3}$to positive logic, and prove various implications and equivalences between them. We also provide a characterisation of stability in positive logic in analogy with the one in full first-order logic, both on the level of formulas and on the level of theories. For simple theories there are the classically equivalent definitions of not having$\mathsf {TP}$and dividing having local character, which we prove to be equivalent in positive logic as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Undefinability of Multiplication in Presburger Arithmetic with Sets of Powers.Chris Schulz - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-15.
    We begin by proving that any Presburger-definable image of one or more sets of powers has zero natural density. Then, by adapting the proof of a dichotomy result on o-minimal structures by Friedman and Miller, we produce a similar dichotomy for expansions of Presburger arithmetic on the integers. Combining these two results, we obtain that the expansion of the ordered group of integers by any number of sets of powers does not define multiplication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Axiomatizing AECs and applications.Samson Leung - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (5):103248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hanf number of the first stability cardinal in AECs.Samson Leung - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (2):103201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Generic variations of models of T.Andreas Baudisch - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1025-1038.
    Let T be a model-complete theory that eliminates the quantifier $\exists^\infty x$ . For T we construct a theory T+ such that any element in a model of T+ determines a model of T. We show that T+ has a model companion T1. We can iterate the construction. The produced theories are investigated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Dividing Line Methodology: Model Theory Motivating Set Theory.John T. Baldwin - 2021 - Theoria 87 (2):361-393.
    We explore Shelah's model‐theoretic dividing line methodology. In particular, we discuss how problems in model theory motivated new techniques in model theory, for example classifying theories by their potential (consistently with Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC)) spectrum of cardinals in which there is a universal model. Two other examples are the study (with Malliaris) of the Keisler order leading to a new ZFC result on cardinal invariants and attempts to clarify the “main gap” by reducing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ramsey transfer to semi-retractions.Lynn Scow - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (3):102891.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A New Perspective on Semi-Retractions and the Ramsey Property.Dana Bartošová & Lynn Scow - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (3):945-979.
    We investigate the notion of a semi-retraction between two first-order structures (in typically different signatures) that was introduced by the second author as a link between the Ramsey property and generalized indiscernible sequences. We look at semi-retractions through a new lens establishing transfers of the Ramsey property and finite Ramsey degrees under quite general conditions that are optimal as demonstrated by counterexamples. Finally, we compare semi-retractions to the category theoretic notion of a pre-adjunction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A proof of morley's conjecture.Bradd Hart - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1346-1358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Countable models of nonmultidimensional ℵ0-stable theories.Elisabeth Bouscaren & Daniel Lascar - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):197-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Independence logic and abstract independence relations.Gianluca Paolini - 2015 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 61 (3):202-216.
    We continue the work on the relations between independence logic and the model-theoretic analysis of independence, generalizing the results of [15] and [16] to the framework of abstract independence relations for an arbitrary AEC. We give a model-theoretic interpretation of the independence atom and characterize under which conditions we can prove a completeness result with respect to the deductive system that axiomatizes independence in team semantics and statistics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Strict independence.Itay Kaplan & Alexander Usvyatsov - 2014 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 14 (2):1450008.
    We investigate the notions of strict independence and strict non-forking, and establish basic properties and connections between the two. In particular, it follows from our investigation that in resilient theories strict non-forking is symmetric. Based on this study, we develop notions of weight which characterize NTP2, dependence and strong dependence. Many of our proofs rely on careful analysis of sequences that witness dividing. We prove simple characterizations of such sequences in resilient theories, as well as of Morley sequences which are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tree indiscernibilities, revisited.Byunghan Kim, Hyeung-Joon Kim & Lynn Scow - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (1-2):211-232.
    We give definitions that distinguish between two notions of indiscernibility for a set {aη∣η∈ω>ω}\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\{a_{\eta} \mid \eta \in ^{\omega>}\omega\}}$$\end{document} that saw original use in Shelah [Classification theory and the number of non-isomorphic models. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1990], which we name s- and str−indiscernibility. Using these definitions and detailed proofs, we prove s- and str-modeling theorems and give applications of these theorems. In particular, we verify a step in the argument that TP is equivalent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Finite and Infinite Model Theory-A Historical Perspective.John Baldwin - 2000 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 8 (5):605-628.
    We describe the progress of model theory in the last half century from the standpoint of how finite model theory might develop.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On VC-minimal theories and variants.Vincent Guingona & Michael C. Laskowski - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (7-8):743-758.
    In this paper, we study VC-minimal theories and explore related concepts. We first define the notion of convex orderablity and show that this lies strictly between VC-minimality and dp-minimality. To do this we prove a general result about set systems with independence dimension ≤ 1. Next, we define the notion of weak VC-minimality, show it lies strictly between VC-minimality and dependence, and show that all unstable weakly VC-minimal theories interpret an infinite linear order. Finally, we define the notion full VC-minimality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Shelah's Categoricity Conjecture from a Successor for Tame Abstract Elementary Classes.Rami Grossberg & Monica Vandieren - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):553 - 568.
    We prove a categoricity transfer theorem for tame abstract elementary classes. Theorem 0.1. Suppose that K is a χ-tame abstract elementary class and satisfies the amalgamation and joint embedding properties and has arbitrarily large models. Let λ ≥ Max{χ.LS(K)⁺}. If K is categorical in λ and λ⁺, then K is categorical in λ⁺⁺. Combining this theorem with some results from [37], we derive a form of Shelah's Categoricity Conjecture for tame abstract elementary classes: Corollary 0.2. Suppose K is a χ-tame (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Set theory and c*-algebras.Nik Weaver - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):1-20.
    We survey the use of extra-set-theoretic hypotheses, mainly the continuum hypothesis, in the C*-algebra literature. The Calkin algebra emerges as a basic object of interest.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On theories having a finite number of nonisomorphic countable models.Akito Tsuboi - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):806-808.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Forking and fundamental order in simple theories.Daniel Lascar & Anand Pillay - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):1155-1158.
    We give a characterisation of forking in the context of simple theories in terms of the fundamental order.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Les automorphismes d'un ensemble fortement minimal.Daniel Lascar - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1):238-251.
    Let M be a countable saturated structure, and assume that D(ν) is a strongly minimal formula (without parameter) such that M is the algebraic closure of D(M). We will prove the two following theorems: Theorem 1. If G is a subgroup of $\operatorname{Aut}(\mathfrak{M})$ of countable index, there exists a finite set A in M such that every A-strong automorphism is in G. Theorem 2. Assume that G is a normal subgroup of $\operatorname{Aut}(\mathfrak{M})$ containing an element g such that for all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Model companions of theories with an automorphism.Hirotaka Kikyo - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1215-1222.
    For a theory T in L, T σ is the theory of the models of T with an automorphism σ. If T is an unstable model complete theory without the independence property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is an unstable model complete theory and T σ has the amalgamation property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is model complete and has the fcp, then T σ has no model completion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Models with second order properties in successors of singulars.Rami Grossberg - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):122-137.
    Let L(Q) be first order logic with Keisler's quantifier, in the λ + interpretation (= the satisfaction is defined as follows: $M \models (\mathbf{Q}x)\varphi(x)$ means there are λ + many elements in M satisfying the formula φ(x)). Theorem 1. Let λ be a singular cardinal; assume □ λ and GCH. If T is a complete theory in L(Q) of cardinality at most λ, and p is an L(Q) 1-type so that T strongly omits $p (= p$ has no support, to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An AEC framework for fields with commuting automorphisms.Tapani Hyttinen & Kaisa Kangas - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (7):1001-1032.
    In this paper, we introduce an AEC framework for studying fields with commuting automorphisms. Fields with commuting automorphisms are closely related to difference fields. Some authors define a difference ring (or field) as a ring (or field) together with several commuting endomorphisms, while others only study one endomorphism. Z. Chatzidakis and E. Hrushovski have studied in depth the model theory of ACFA, the model companion of difference fields with one automorphism. Our fields with commuting automorphisms generalize this setting. We have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Co-theory of sorted profinite groups for PAC structures.Daniel Max Hoffmann & Junguk Lee - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (3).
    We achieve several results. First, we develop a variant of the theory of absolute Galois groups in the context of many sorted structures. Second, we provide a method for coding absolute Galois groups of structures, so they can be interpreted in some monster model with an additional predicate. Third, we prove the “Weak Independence Theorem” for pseudo-algebraically closed (PAC) substructures of an ambient structure with no finite cover property (nfcp) and the property [Formula: see text]. Fourth, we describe Kim-dividing in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reducts of structures and maximal-closed permutation groups.Manuel Bodirsky & Dugald Macpherson - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (3):1087-1114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A preservation theorem for theories without the tree property of the first kind.Jan Dobrowolski & Hyeungjoon Kim - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (6):536-543.
    We prove the NTP1 property of a geometric theory T is inherited by theories of lovely pairs and H‐structures associated to T. We also provide a class of examples of nonsimple geometric NTP1 theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem for infinitary theories which have the unsuperstability property.Rami Grossberg - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):231-242.
    We present a downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem which transfers downward formulas from L ∞,ω to L κ +, ω . The simplest instance is: Theorem 1. Let $\lambda > \kappa$ be infinite cardinals, and let L be a similarity type of cardinality κ at most. For every L-structure M of cardinality λ and every $X \subseteq M$ there exists a model $N \prec M$ containing the set X of power |X| · κ such that for every pair of finite sequences a, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Completeness and categoricity (in power): Formalization without foundationalism.John T. Baldwin - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):39-79.
    We propose a criterion to regard a property of a theory (in first or second order logic) as virtuous: the property must have significant mathematical consequences for the theory (or its models). We then rehearse results of Ajtai, Marek, Magidor, H. Friedman and Solovay to argue that for second order logic, ‘categoricity’ has little virtue. For first order logic, categoricity is trivial; but ‘categoricity in power’ has enormous structural consequences for any of the theories satisfying it. The stability hierarchy extends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Canonical forking in AECs.Will Boney, Rami Grossberg, Alexei Kolesnikov & Sebastien Vasey - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (7):590-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On a common generalization of Shelah's 2-rank, dp-rank, and o-minimal dimension.Vincent Guingona & Cameron Donnay Hill - 2015 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 166 (4):502-525.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Theories without the tree property of the second kind.Artem Chernikov - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):695-723.
    We initiate a systematic study of the class of theories without the tree property of the second kind — NTP2. Most importantly, we show: the burden is “sub-multiplicative” in arbitrary theories ; NTP2 is equivalent to the generalized Kimʼs lemma and to the boundedness of ist-weight; the dp-rank of a type in an arbitrary theory is witnessed by mutually indiscernible sequences of realizations of the type, after adding some parameters — so the dp-rank of a 1-type in any theory is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • A dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers.Ilijas Farah & Saharon Shelah - 2010 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 10 (1):45-81.
    We prove a strong dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers of a given model of cardinality ≤ 2ℵ0 associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters on ℕ. They are either all isomorphic, or else there are 22ℵ0 many nonisomorphic ultrapowers. We prove the analogous result for metric structures, including C*-algebras and II1 factors, as well as their relative commutants and include several applications. We also show that the CAF001-algebra [Formula: see text] always has nonisomorphic relative commutants in its ultrapowers associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A geometric introduction to forking and thorn-forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):1-20.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • On the number of independent partitions.Akito Tsuboi - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):809-814.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From stability to simplicity.Byunghan Kim & Anand Pillay - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (1):17-36.
    §1. Introduction. In this report we wish to describe recent work on a class of first order theories first introduced by Shelah in [32], the simple theories. Major progress was made in the first author's doctoral thesis [17]. We will give a survey of this, as well as further works by the authors and others.The class of simple theories includes stable theories, but also many more, such as the theory of the random graph. Moreover, many of the theories of particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Classification and interpretation.Andreas Baudisch - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):138-159.
    Let S and T be countable complete theories. We assume that T is superstable without the dimensional order property, and S is interpretable in T in such a way that every model of S is coded in a model of T. We show that S does not have the dimensional order property, and we discuss the question of whether $\operatorname{Depth}(S) \leq \operatorname{Depth}(T)$ . For Mekler's uniform interpretation of arbitrary theories S of finite similarity type into suitable theories T s of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations