Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Theories without the tree property of the second kind.Artem Chernikov - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):695-723.
    We initiate a systematic study of the class of theories without the tree property of the second kind — NTP2. Most importantly, we show: the burden is “sub-multiplicative” in arbitrary theories ; NTP2 is equivalent to the generalized Kimʼs lemma and to the boundedness of ist-weight; the dp-rank of a type in an arbitrary theory is witnessed by mutually indiscernible sequences of realizations of the type, after adding some parameters — so the dp-rank of a 1-type in any theory is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Some coinductive graphs.A. H. Lachlan - 1990 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 29 (4):213-229.
    LetT be a universal theory of graphs such that Mod(T) is closed under disjoint unions. Letℳ T be a disjoint union ℳ i such that eachℳ i is a finite model ofT and every finite isomorphism type in Mod(T) is represented in{ℳ i ∶i<Ω3}. We investigate under what conditions onT, Th(ℳ T ) is a coinductive theory, where a theory is called coinductive if it can be axiomatizated by ∃∀-sentences. We also characterize coinductive graphs which have quantifier-free rank 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On VC-minimal theories and variants.Vincent Guingona & Michael C. Laskowski - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (7-8):743-758.
    In this paper, we study VC-minimal theories and explore related concepts. We first define the notion of convex orderablity and show that this lies strictly between VC-minimality and dp-minimality. To do this we prove a general result about set systems with independence dimension ≤ 1. Next, we define the notion of weak VC-minimality, show it lies strictly between VC-minimality and dependence, and show that all unstable weakly VC-minimal theories interpret an infinite linear order. Finally, we define the notion full VC-minimality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Shelah's stability spectrum and homogeneity spectrum in finite diagrams.Rami Grossberg & Olivier Lessmann - 2002 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 41 (1):1-31.
    We present Saharon Shelah's Stability Spectrum and Homogeneity Spectrum theorems, as well as the equivalence between the order property and instability in the framework of Finite Diagrams. Finite Diagrams is a context which generalizes the first order case. Localized versions of these theorems are presented. Our presentation is based on several papers; the point of view is contemporary and some of the proofs are new. The treatment of local stability in Finite Diagrams is new.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Categoricity transfer in simple finitary abstract elementary classes.Tapani Hyttinen & Meeri Kesälä - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (3):759 - 806.
    We continue our study of finitary abstract elementary classes, defined in [7]. In this paper, we prove a categoricity transfer theorem for a case of simple finitary AECs. We introduce the concepts of weak κ-categoricity and f-primary models to the framework of א₀-stable simple finitary AECs with the extension property, whereby we gain the following theorem: Let (������, ≼ ������ ) be a simple finitary AEC, weakly categorical in some uncountable κ. Then (������, ≼ ������ ) is weakly categorical in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On uniform definability of types over finite sets.Vincent Guingona - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):499-514.
    In this paper, using definability of types over indiscernible sequences as a template, we study a property of formulas and theories called "uniform definability of types over finite sets" (UDTFS). We explore UDTFS and show how it relates to well-known properties in model theory. We recall that stable theories and weakly o-minimal theories have UDTFS and UDTFS implies dependence. We then show that all dp-minimal theories have UDTFS.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Generic variations of models of T.Andreas Baudisch - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1025-1038.
    Let T be a model-complete theory that eliminates the quantifier $\exists^\infty x$ . For T we construct a theory T+ such that any element in a model of T+ determines a model of T. We show that T+ has a model companion T1. We can iterate the construction. The produced theories are investigated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Subsets of superstable structures are weakly benign.Bektur Baizhanov, John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (1):142-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Local homogeneity.Bektur Baizhanov & John T. Baldwin - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (4):1243-1260.
    We study the expansion of stable structures by adding predicates for arbitrary subsets. Generalizing work of Poizat-Bouscaren on the one hand and Baldwin-Benedikt-Casanovas-Ziegler on the other we provide a sufficient condition for such an expansion to be stable. This generalization weakens the original definitions in two ways: dealing with arbitrary subsets rather than just submodels and removing the ‘small' or ‘belles paires' hypothesis. We use this generalization to characterize in terms of pairs, the ‘triviality' of the geometry on a strongly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Set theory and c*-algebras.Nik Weaver - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):1-20.
    We survey the use of extra-set-theoretic hypotheses, mainly the continuum hypothesis, in the C*-algebra literature. The Calkin algebra emerges as a basic object of interest.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Independence results.Saharon Shelah - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):563-573.
    We prove independence results concerning the number of nonisomorphic models (using the S-chain condition and S-properness) and the consistency of "ZCF + 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 2 + there is a universal linear order of power ℵ 1 ". Most of these results were announced in [Sh 4], [Sh 5]. In subsequent papers we shall prove an analog f MA for forcing which does not destroy stationary subsets of ω 1 , investigate D-properness for various filters and prove the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Some remarks on definable equivalence relations in o-minimal structures.Anand Pillay - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):709-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Closed sets and chain conditions in stable theories.Anand Pillay & Gabriel Srour - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1350-1362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The baire category theorem and cardinals of countable cofinality.Arnold W. Miller - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):275-288.
    Let κ B be the least cardinal for which the Baire category theorem fails for the real line R. Thus κ B is the least κ such that the real line can be covered by κ many nowhere dense sets. It is shown that κ B cannot have countable cofinality. On the other hand it is consistent that the corresponding cardinal for 2 ω 1 be ℵ ω . Similar questions are considered for the ideal of measure zero sets, other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Complete theories with only universal and existential axioms.A. H. Lachlan - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):698-711.
    Let T be a complete first-order theory over a finite relational language which is axiomatized by universal and existential sentences. It is shown that T is almost trivial in the sense that the universe of any model of T can be written $F \overset{\cdot}{\cup} I_1 \overset{\cdot}{\cup} I_2 \overset{\cdot}{\cup} \cdots \overset{\cdot}{\cup} I_n$ , where F is finite and I 1 , I 2 ,...,I n are mutually indiscernible over F. Some results about complete theories with ∃∀-axioms over a finite relational language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The strict order property and generic automorphisms.Hirotaka Kikyo & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (1):214-216.
    If T is a model complete theory with the strict order property, then the theory of the models of T with an automorphism has no model companion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On regular reduced products.Juliette Kennedy & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1169-1177.
    Assume $\langle \aleph_0, \aleph_1 \rangle \rightarrow \langle \lambda, \lambda^+ \rangle$ . Assume M is a model of a first order theory T of cardinality at most λ+ in a language L(T) of cardinality $\leq \lambda$ . Let N be a model with the same language. Let Δ be a set of first order formulas in L(T) and let D be a regular filter on λ. Then M is $\Delta-embeddable$ into the reduced power $N^\lambda/D$ , provided that every $\Delta-existential$ formula true (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Remarks on weak notions of saturation in models of peano arithmetic.Matt Kaufmann & James H. Schmerl - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):129-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Alfred Tarski and decidable theories.John Doner & Wilfrid Hodges - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):20-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Quasi-o-minimal structures.Oleg Belegradek, Ya'acov Peterzil & Frank Wagner - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1115-1132.
    A structure (M, $ ,...) is called quasi-o-minimal if in any structure elementarily equivalent to it the definable subsets are exactly the Boolean combinations of 0-definable subsets and intervals. We give a series of natural examples of quasi-o-minimal structures which are not o-minimal; one of them is the ordered group of integers. We develop a technique to investigate quasi-o-minimality and use it to study quasi-o-minimal ordered groups (possibly with extra structure). Main results: any quasi-o-minimal ordered group is abelian; any quasi-o-minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Dividing Lines Between Positive Theories.Anna Dmitrieva, Francesco Gallinaro & Mark Kamsma - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-25.
    We generalise the properties $\mathsf {OP}$, $\mathsf {IP}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}$, $\mathsf {TP}_{1}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}_{2}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{1}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{2}$, and $\mathsf {SOP}_{3}$ to positive logic, and prove various implications and equivalences between them. We also provide a characterisation of stability in positive logic in analogy with the one in full first-order logic, both on the level of formulas and on the level of theories. For simple theories there are the classically equivalent definitions of not having $\mathsf {TP}$ and dividing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ramsey transfer to semi-retractions.Lynn Scow - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (3):102891.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ordered asymptotic classes of finite structures.Darío García - 2020 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 171 (4):102776.
    We introduce the concept of o-asymptotic classes of finite structures, melding ideas coming from 1-dimensional asymptotic classes and o-minimality. Along with several examples and non-examples of these classes, we present some classification theory results of their infinite ultraproducts: Every infinite ultraproduct of structures in an o-asymptotic class is superrosy of U^þ-rank 1, and NTP2 (in fact, inp-minimal).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equivalent definitions of superstability in Tame abstract elementary classes.Rami Grossberg & Sebastien Vasey - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (4):1387-1408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Reduction of database independence to dividing in atomless Boolean algebras.Tapani Hyttinen & Gianluca Paolini - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):505-518.
    We prove that the form of conditional independence at play in database theory and independence logic is reducible to the first-order dividing calculus in the theory of atomless Boolean algebras. This establishes interesting connections between independence in database theory and stochastic independence. As indeed, in light of the aforementioned reduction and recent work of Ben-Yaacov :957–1012, 2013), the former case of independence can be seen as the discrete version of the latter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the number of nonisomorphic models of an infinitary theory which has the infinitary order property. Part A.Rami Grossberg & Saharon Shelah - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):302-322.
    Let κ and λ be infinite cardinals such that κ ≤ λ (we have new information for the case when $\kappa ). Let T be a theory in L κ +, ω of cardinality at most κ, let φ(x̄, ȳ) ∈ L λ +, ω . Now define $\mu^\ast_\varphi (\lambda, T) = \operatorname{Min} \{\mu^\ast:$ If T satisfies $(\forall\mu \kappa)(\exists M_\chi \models T)(\exists \{a_i: i Our main concept in this paper is $\mu^\ast_\varphi (\lambda, \kappa) = \operatorname{Sup}\{\mu^\ast(\lambda, T): T$ is a theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On nontrivial types of U-rank 1.Steven Buechler - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (2):548-551.
    Theorem A. Suppose that T is superstable and p is a nontrivial type of U-rank 1. Then R(p, L, ∞) = 1. Theorem B. Suppose that T is totally transcendental and p is a nontrivial type of U-rank 1. Then p has Morley rank 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Completeness and categoricity (in power): Formalization without foundationalism.John T. Baldwin - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):39-79.
    We propose a criterion to regard a property of a theory (in first or second order logic) as virtuous: the property must have significant mathematical consequences for the theory (or its models). We then rehearse results of Ajtai, Marek, Magidor, H. Friedman and Solovay to argue that for second order logic, ‘categoricity’ has little virtue. For first order logic, categoricity is trivial; but ‘categoricity in power’ has enormous structural consequences for any of the theories satisfying it. The stability hierarchy extends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Canonical forking in AECs.Will Boney, Rami Grossberg, Alexei Kolesnikov & Sebastien Vasey - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (7):590-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Tree indiscernibilities, revisited.Byunghan Kim, Hyeung-Joon Kim & Lynn Scow - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (1-2):211-232.
    We give definitions that distinguish between two notions of indiscernibility for a set {aη∣η∈ω>ω}\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\{a_{\eta} \mid \eta \in ^{\omega>}\omega\}}$$\end{document} that saw original use in Shelah [Classification theory and the number of non-isomorphic models. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1990], which we name s- and str−indiscernibility. Using these definitions and detailed proofs, we prove s- and str-modeling theorems and give applications of these theorems. In particular, we verify a step in the argument that TP is equivalent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Fundamentals of forking.Victor Harnik & Leo Harrington - 1984 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 26 (3):245-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Toward categoricity for classes with no maximal models.Saharon Shelah & Andrés Villaveces - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 97 (1-3):1-25.
    We provide here the first steps toward a Classification Theory ofElementary Classes with no maximal models, plus some mild set theoretical assumptions, when the class is categorical in some λ greater than its Löwenheim-Skolem number. We study the degree to which amalgamation may be recovered, the behaviour of non μ-splitting types. Most importantly, the existence of saturated models in a strong enough sense is proved, as a first step toward a complete solution to the o Conjecture for these classes. Further (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • On properties of theories which preclude the existence of universal models.Mirna Džamonja & Saharon Shelah - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 139 (1):280-302.
    We introduce the oak property of first order theories, which is a syntactical condition that we show to be sufficient for a theory not to have universal models in cardinality λ when certain cardinal arithmetic assumptions about λ implying the failure of GCH hold. We give two examples of theories that have the oak property and show that none of these examples satisfy SOP4, not even SOP3. This is related to the question of the connection of the property SOP4 to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hypergraph sequences as a tool for saturation of ultrapowers.M. E. Malliaris - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):195-223.
    Let T 1 , T 2 be countable first-order theories, M i ⊨ T i , and ������ any regular ultrafilter on λ ≥ $\aleph_{0}$ . A longstanding open problem of Keisler asks when T 2 is more complex than T 1 , as measured by the fact that for any such λ, ������, if the ultrapower (M 2 ) λ /������ realizes all types over sets of size ≤ λ, then so must the ultrapower (M 1 ) λ /������. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Categoricity and ranks.Jürgen Saffe - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1379-1392.
    In this paper we investigate the connections between categoricity and ranks. We use stability theory to prove some old and new results.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sous-groupes définissables d'un groupe stable.Bruno Poizat - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (1):137-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • First order topological structures and theories.Anand Pillay - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):763-778.
    In this paper we introduce the notion of a first order topological structure, and consider various possible conditions on the complexity of the definable sets in such a structure, drawing several consequences thereof.Our aim is to develop, for a restricted class of unstable theories, results analogous to those for stable theories. The “material basis” for such an endeavor is the analogy between the field of real numbers and the field of complex numbers, the former being a “nicely behaved” unstable structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Meager sets on the hyperfinite time line.H. Jerome Keisler & Steven C. Leth - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):71-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Expansion of a model of a weakly o-minimal theory by a family of unary predicates.Bektur Sembiuly Baizhanov - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1382-1414.
    A subset A $\subseteq$ M of a totally ordered structure M is said to be convex, if for any a, b $\in A: [a . A complete theory of first order is weakly o-minimal (M. Dickmann [D]) if any model M is totally ordered by some $\emptyset$ -definable formula and any subset of M which is definable with parameters from M is a finite union of convex sets. We prove here that for any model M of a weakly o-minimal theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Rich models.Michael H. Albert & Rami P. Grossberg - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1292-1298.
    We define a rich model to be one which contains a proper elementary substructure isomorphic to itself. Existence, nonstructure, and categoricity theorems for rich models are proved. A theory T which has fewer than $\min(2^\lambda,\beth_2)$ rich models of cardinality $\lambda(\lambda > |T|)$ is totally transcendental. We show that a countable theory with a unique rich model in some uncountable cardinal is categorical in ℵ 1 and also has a unique countable rich model. We also consider a stronger notion of richness, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Around Logical Perfection.John A. Cruz Morales, Andrés Villaveces & Boris Zilber - 2021 - Theoria 87 (4):971-985.
    Theoria, Volume 87, Issue 4, Page 971-985, August 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Around Logical Perfection.John A. Cruz Morales, Andrés Villaveces & Boris Zilber - 2021 - Theoria 87 (4):971-985.
    In this article we present a notion of “logical perfection”. We first describe through examples a notion of logical perfection extracted from the contemporary logical concept of categoricity. Categoricity (in power) has become in the past half century a main driver of ideas in model theory, both mathematically (stability theory may be regarded as a way of approximating categoricity) and philosophically. In the past two decades, categoricity notions have started to overlap with more classical notions of robustness and smoothness. These (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The number of pairwise non-elementarily-embeddable models.Saharon Shelah - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1431-1455.
    We get consistency results on I(λ, T 1 , T) under the assumption that D(T) has cardinality $>|T|$ . We get positive results and consistency results on IE(λ, T 1 , T). The interest is model-theoretic, but the content is mostly set-theoretic: in Theorems 1-3, combinatorial; in Theorems 4-7 and 11(2), to prove consistency of counterexamples we concentrate on forcing arguments; and in Theorems 8-10 and 11(1), combinatorics for counterexamples; the rest are discussion and problems. In particular: (A) By Theorems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Upward Morley's theorem downward.Gábor Sági & Zalán Gyenis - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (4-5):303-331.
    By a celebrated theorem of Morley, a theory T is ℵ1‐categorical if and only if it is κ‐categorical for all uncountable κ. In this paper we are taking the first steps towards extending Morley's categoricity theorem “to the finite”. In more detail, we are presenting conditions, implying that certain finite subsets of certain ℵ1‐categorical T have at most one n‐element model for each natural number (counting up to isomorphism, of course).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strongly 2-dimensional theories.Akito Tsuboi - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):931-936.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hanf number of omitting type for simple first-order theories.Saharon Shelah - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):319-324.
    Let T be a complete countable first-order theory such that every ultrapower of a model of T is saturated. If T has a model omitting a type p in every cardinality $ then T has a model omitting p in every cardinality. There is also a related theorem, and an example showing the $\beth_\omega$ cannot be improved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Countable structures of given age.H. D. Macpherson, M. Pouzet & R. E. Woodrow - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):992-1010.
    Let L be a finite relational language. The age of a structure M over L is the set of isomorphism types of finite substructures of M. We classify those ages U for which there are less than 2ω countably infinite pairwise nonisomorphic L-structures of age U.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Model companions of theories with an automorphism.Hirotaka Kikyo - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1215-1222.
    For a theory T in L, T σ is the theory of the models of T with an automorphism σ. If T is an unstable model complete theory without the independence property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is an unstable model complete theory and T σ has the amalgamation property, then T σ has no model companion. If T is model complete and has the fcp, then T σ has no model completion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Weight ω in stable theories with few types.Bernhard Herwig - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):353-373.
    We construct a type p with preweight ω with respect to itself in a theory with few types. A type with this property must be present in a stable theory with finitely many (but more than one) countable models. The construction is a modification of Hrushovski's important pseudoplane construction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The classification of excellent classes.R. Grossberg & B. Hart - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1359-1381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations