Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Quasi-o-minimal structures.Oleg Belegradek, Ya'acov Peterzil & Frank Wagner - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1115-1132.
    A structure (M, $ ,...) is called quasi-o-minimal if in any structure elementarily equivalent to it the definable subsets are exactly the Boolean combinations of 0-definable subsets and intervals. We give a series of natural examples of quasi-o-minimal structures which are not o-minimal; one of them is the ordered group of integers. We develop a technique to investigate quasi-o-minimality and use it to study quasi-o-minimal ordered groups (possibly with extra structure). Main results: any quasi-o-minimal ordered group is abelian; any quasi-o-minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Partitioning subsets of stable models.Timothy Bays - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1899-1908.
    This paper discusses two combinatorial problems in stability theory. First we prove a partition result for subsets of stable models: for any A and B, we can partition A into |B |<κ(T ) pieces, Ai | i < |B |<κ(T ) , such that for each Ai there is a Bi ⊆ B where |Bi| < κ(T ) and Ai..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On two hierarchies of dimensions.Andreas Baudisch - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):959-968.
    Let T be a countable, complete, ω-stable, nonmultidimensional theory. By Lascar [7], in T eq there is in every dimension of T a type with Lascar rank ω α for some α. We give sufficient conditions for α to coincide with the level of that dimension in Pillay's [10] RK-hierarchy of dimensions computed in T eq . In particular, this is fulfilled for modules.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The spectrum of resplendency.John T. Baldwin - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):626-636.
    Let T be a complete countable first order theory and λ an uncountable cardinal. Theorem 1. If T is not superstable, T has 2 λ resplendent models of power λ. Theorem 2. If T is strictly superstable, then T has at least $\min(2^\lambda,\beth_2)$ resplendent models of power λ. Theorem 3. If T is not superstable or is small and strictly superstable, then every resplendent homogeneous model of T is saturated. Theorem 4 (with Knight). For each μ ∈ ω ∪ {ω, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Diverse classes.John T. Baldwin - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):875-893.
    Let $\mathbf{I}(\mu,K)$ denote the number of nonisomorphic models of power $\mu$ and $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K)$ the number of nonmutually embeddable models. We define in this paper the notion of a diverse class and use it to prove a number of results. The major result is Theorem B: For any diverse class $K$ and $\mu$ greater than the cardinality of the language of $K$, $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K) \geq \min(2^\mu,\beth_2).$ From it we deduce both an old result of Shelah, Theorem C: If $T$ is countable and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Dividing Lines Between Positive Theories.Anna Dmitrieva, Francesco Gallinaro & Mark Kamsma - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-25.
    We generalise the properties $\mathsf {OP}$, $\mathsf {IP}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}$, $\mathsf {TP}_{1}$, k- $\mathsf {TP}_{2}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{1}$, $\mathsf {SOP}_{2}$, and $\mathsf {SOP}_{3}$ to positive logic, and prove various implications and equivalences between them. We also provide a characterisation of stability in positive logic in analogy with the one in full first-order logic, both on the level of formulas and on the level of theories. For simple theories there are the classically equivalent definitions of not having $\mathsf {TP}$ and dividing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Turing Degrees and Keisler’s Order.Maryanthe Malliaris & Saharon Shelah - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):331-341.
    There is a Turing functional $\Phi $ taking $A^\prime $ to a theory $T_A$ whose complexity is exactly that of the jump of A, and which has the property that $A \leq _T B$ if and only if $T_A \trianglelefteq T_B$ in Keisler’s order. In fact, by more elaborate means and related theories, we may keep the complexity at the level of A without using the jump.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dividing lines in unstable theories and subclasses of Baire 1 functions.Karim Khanaki - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (7):977-993.
    We give a new characterization of _SOP_ (the strict order property) in terms of the behaviour of formulas in any model of the theory as opposed to having to look at the behaviour of indiscernible sequences inside saturated ones. We refine a theorem of Shelah, namely a theory has _OP_ (the order property) if and only if it has _IP_ (the independence property) or _SOP_, in several ways by characterizing various notions in functional analytic style. We point out some connections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hanf numbers for extendibility and related phenomena.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (3):437-464.
    This paper contains portions of Baldwin’s talk at the Set Theory and Model Theory Conference and a detailed proof that in a suitable extension of ZFC, there is a complete sentence of \ that has maximal models in cardinals cofinal in the first measurable cardinal and, of course, never again.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Atom-canonicity in varieties of cylindric algebras with applications to omitting types in multi-modal logic.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2020 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 30 (3):223-271.
    Fix 2 < n < ω and let C A n denote the class of cylindric algebras of dimension n. Roughly, C A n is the algebraic counterpart of the proof theory of first-order logic restricted to the first n var...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On some dynamical aspects of NIP theories.Alireza Mofidi - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (1-2):37-71.
    We investigate some dynamical features of the actions of automorphisms in the context of model theory. We interpret a few notions such as compact systems, entropy and symbolic representations from the theory of dynamical systems in the realm of model theory. In this direction, we settle a number of characterizations of NIP theories in terms of dynamics of automorphisms and invariant measures. For example, it is shown that the property of NIP corresponds to the compactness property of some associated systems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Superstability from categoricity in abstract elementary classes.Will Boney, Rami Grossberg, Monica M. VanDieren & Sebastien Vasey - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (7):1383-1395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Shelah's eventual categoricity conjecture in universal classes: Part I.Sebastien Vasey - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (9):1609-1642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Pseudo real closed fields, pseudo p-adically closed fields and NTP2.Samaria Montenegro - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (1):191-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Finite and Infinite Model Theory-A Historical Perspective.John Baldwin - 2000 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 8 (5):605-628.
    We describe the progress of model theory in the last half century from the standpoint of how finite model theory might develop.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward classifying unstable theories.Saharon Shelah - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 80 (3):229-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unstable theories.Tapani Hyttinen & Heikki Tuuri - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 52 (3):203-248.
    If T is an unstable theory of cardinality <λ or countable stable theory with OTOP or countable superstable theory with DOP, λω λω1 in the superstable with DOP case) is regular and λ<λ=λ, then we construct for T strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models of cardinality λ. This can be viewed as a strong nonstructure theorem for such theories. We also consider the case when T is unsuperstable and develop further a result of Shelah about the existence of L∞,λ-equivalent nonisomorphic models for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Categoricity for abstract classes with amalgamation.Saharon Shelah - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 98 (1-3):261-294.
    Let be an abstract elementary class with amalgamation, and Lowenheim Skolem number LS. We prove that for a suitable Hanf number gc0 if χ0 < λ0 λ1, and is categorical inλ1+ then it is categorical in λ0.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • On properties of theories which preclude the existence of universal models.Mirna Džamonja & Saharon Shelah - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 139 (1):280-302.
    We introduce the oak property of first order theories, which is a syntactical condition that we show to be sufficient for a theory not to have universal models in cardinality λ when certain cardinal arithmetic assumptions about λ implying the failure of GCH hold. We give two examples of theories that have the oak property and show that none of these examples satisfy SOP4, not even SOP3. This is related to the question of the connection of the property SOP4 to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Shelah's stability spectrum and homogeneity spectrum in finite diagrams.Rami Grossberg & Olivier Lessmann - 2002 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 41 (1):1-31.
    We present Saharon Shelah's Stability Spectrum and Homogeneity Spectrum theorems, as well as the equivalence between the order property and instability in the framework of Finite Diagrams. Finite Diagrams is a context which generalizes the first order case. Localized versions of these theorems are presented. Our presentation is based on several papers; the point of view is contemporary and some of the proofs are new. The treatment of local stability in Finite Diagrams is new.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Model Companions of for Stable T.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (3):129-142.
    We introduce the notion T does not omit obstructions. If a stable theory does not admit obstructions then it does not have the finite cover property (nfcp). For any theory T, form a new theory by adding a new unary function symbol and axioms asserting it is an automorphism. The main result of the paper asserts the following: If T is a stable theory, T does not admit obstructions if and only if has a model companion. The proof involves some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers.Ilijas Farah & Saharon Shelah - 2010 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 10 (1):45-81.
    We prove a strong dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers of a given model of cardinality ≤ 2ℵ0 associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters on ℕ. They are either all isomorphic, or else there are 22ℵ0 many nonisomorphic ultrapowers. We prove the analogous result for metric structures, including C*-algebras and II1 factors, as well as their relative commutants and include several applications. We also show that the CAF001-algebra [Formula: see text] always has nonisomorphic relative commutants in its ultrapowers associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Stable types in rosy theories.Assaf Hasson & Alf Onshuus - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (4):1211-1230.
    We study the behaviour of stable types in rosy theories. The main technical result is that a non-þ-forking extension of an unstable type is unstable. We apply this to show that a rosy group with a þ-generic stable type is stable. In the context of super-rosy theories of finite rank we conclude that non-trivial stable types of U þ -rank 1 must arise from definable stable sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Independence property and hyperbolic groups.Eric Jaligot, Alexey Muranov & Azadeh Neman - 2008 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):88 - 98.
    In continuation of [JOH04, OH07], we prove that existentially closed CSA-groups have the independence property. This is done by showing that there exist words having the independence property relative to the class of torsion-free hyperbolic groups.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thorn-forking as local forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):21-38.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A geometric introduction to forking and thorn-forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):1-20.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Categoricity from one successor cardinal in Tame abstract elementary classes.Rami Grossberg & Monica Vandieren - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (2):181-201.
    We prove that from categoricity in λ+ we can get categoricity in all cardinals ≥ λ+ in a χ-tame abstract elementary classe [Formula: see text] which has arbitrarily large models and satisfies the amalgamation and joint embedding properties, provided [Formula: see text] and λ ≥ χ. For the missing case when [Formula: see text], we prove that [Formula: see text] is totally categorical provided that [Formula: see text] is categorical in [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Automorphism–invariant measures on ℵ0-categorical structures without the independence property.Douglas E. Ensley - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):640 - 652.
    We address the classification of the possible finitely-additive probability measures on the Boolean algebra of definable subsets of M which are invariant under the natural action of $\operatorname{Aut}(M)$ . This pursuit requires a generalization of Shelah's forking formulas [8] to "essentially measure zero" sets and an application of Myer's "rank diagram" [5] of the Boolean algebra under consideration. The classification is completed for a large class of ℵ 0 -categorical structures without the independence property including those which are stable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On theories having a finite number of nonisomorphic countable models.Akito Tsuboi - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):806-808.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Closed sets and chain conditions in stable theories.Anand Pillay & Gabriel Srour - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1350-1362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Some remarks on definable equivalence relations in o-minimal structures.Anand Pillay - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):709-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Théories d'arbres.Michel Parigot - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):841-853.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The baire category theorem and cardinals of countable cofinality.Arnold W. Miller - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):275-288.
    Let κ B be the least cardinal for which the Baire category theorem fails for the real line R. Thus κ B is the least κ such that the real line can be covered by κ many nowhere dense sets. It is shown that κ B cannot have countable cofinality. On the other hand it is consistent that the corresponding cardinal for 2 ω 1 be ℵ ω . Similar questions are considered for the ideal of measure zero sets, other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Vaught's conjecture for o-minimal theories.Laura L. Mayer - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):146-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uncountable theories that are categorical in a higher power.Michael Chris Laskowski - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):512-530.
    In this paper we prove three theorems about first-order theories that are categorical in a higher power. The first theorem asserts that such a theory either is totally categorical or there exist prime and minimal models over arbitrary base sets. The second theorem shows that such theories have a natural notion of dimension that determines the models of the theory up to isomorphism. From this we conclude that $I(T, \aleph_\alpha) = \aleph_0 +|\alpha|$ where ℵ α = the number of formulas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Forking and fundamental order in simple theories.Daniel Lascar & Anand Pillay - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):1155-1158.
    We give a characterisation of forking in the context of simple theories in terms of the fundamental order.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quelques précisions sur la D.o.P. Et la profondeur d'une theorie.D. Lascar - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):316-330.
    We give here alternative definitions for the notions that S. Shelah has introduced in recent papers: the dimensional order property and the depth of a theory. We will also give a proof that the depth of a countable theory, when defined, is an ordinal recursive in T.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The strict order property and generic automorphisms.Hirotaka Kikyo & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (1):214-216.
    If T is a model complete theory with the strict order property, then the theory of the models of T with an automorphism has no model companion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Models with second order properties in successors of singulars.Rami Grossberg - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):122-137.
    Let L(Q) be first order logic with Keisler's quantifier, in the λ + interpretation (= the satisfaction is defined as follows: $M \models (\mathbf{Q}x)\varphi(x)$ means there are λ + many elements in M satisfying the formula φ(x)). Theorem 1. Let λ be a singular cardinal; assume □ λ and GCH. If T is a complete theory in L(Q) of cardinality at most λ, and p is an L(Q) 1-type so that T strongly omits $p (= p$ has no support, to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On chains of relatively saturated submodels of a model without the order property.Rami Grossberg - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):124-128.
    Let M be a given model with similarity type L = L(M), and let L' be any fragment of L |L(M)| +, ω of cardinality |L(M)|. We call $N \prec M L'$ -relatively saturated $\operatorname{iff}$ for every $B \subseteq N$ of cardinality less than | N | every L'-type over B which is realized in M is realized in M is realized in N. We discuss the existence of such submodels. The following are corollaries of the existence theorems. (1) If (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Maximal chains in the fundamental order.Steven Buechler - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):323-326.
    Suppose T is superstable. Let ≤ denote the fundamental order on complete types, [ p] the class of the bound of p, and U(--) Lascar's foundation rank (see [LP]). We prove THEOREM 1. If $q and there is no r such that $q , then U(q) + 1 = U(p). THEOREM 2. Suppose $U(p) and $\xi_1 is a maximal descending chain in the fundamental order with ξ κ = [ p]. Then k = U(p). That the finiteness of U(p) in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A construction of superstable NDOP-NOTOP groups.Andreas Baudisch - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1385-1390.
    The paper continues [1]. Let S be a complete theory of ultraflat (e.g. planar) graphs as introduced in [4]. We show a strong form of NOTOP for S: The union of two models M1 and M2, independent over a common elementary submodel M0, is the primary model over M1 ∪ M2 of S. Then by results of [1] Mekler's construction [6] gives for such a theory S of nice ultraflat graphs a superstable 2-step-nilpotent group of exponent $p (>2)$ with NDOP (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Classification and interpretation.Andreas Baudisch - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):138-159.
    Let S and T be countable complete theories. We assume that T is superstable without the dimensional order property, and S is interpretable in T in such a way that every model of S is coded in a model of T. We show that S does not have the dimensional order property, and we discuss the question of whether $\operatorname{Depth}(S) \leq \operatorname{Depth}(T)$ . For Mekler's uniform interpretation of arbitrary theories S of finite similarity type into suitable theories T s of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • DOP and FCP in generic structures.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (2):427-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Expansion of a model of a weakly o-minimal theory by a family of unary predicates.Bektur Sembiuly Baizhanov - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1382-1414.
    A subset A $\subseteq$ M of a totally ordered structure M is said to be convex, if for any a, b $\in A: [a . A complete theory of first order is weakly o-minimal (M. Dickmann [D]) if any model M is totally ordered by some $\emptyset$ -definable formula and any subset of M which is definable with parameters from M is a finite union of convex sets. We prove here that for any model M of a weakly o-minimal theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Undefinability of Multiplication in Presburger Arithmetic with Sets of Powers.Chris Schulz - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-15.
    We begin by proving that any Presburger-definable image of one or more sets of powers has zero natural density. Then, by adapting the proof of a dichotomy result on o-minimal structures by Friedman and Miller, we produce a similar dichotomy for expansions of Presburger arithmetic on the integers. Combining these two results, we obtain that the expansion of the ordered group of integers by any number of sets of powers does not define multiplication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nsop-Like Independence in Aecats.Mark Kamsma - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (2):724-757.
    The classes stable, simple, and NSOP $_1$ in the stability hierarchy for first-order theories can be characterised by the existence of a certain independence relation. For each of them there is a canonicity theorem: there can be at most one nice independence relation. Independence in stable and simple first-order theories must come from forking and dividing (which then coincide), and for NSOP $_1$ theories it must come from Kim-dividing. We generalise this work to the framework of Abstract Elementary Categories (AECats) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Induced and higher-dimensional stable independence.Michael Lieberman, Jiří Rosický & Sebastien Vasey - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (7):103124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nonstandard methods for finite structures.Akito Tsuboi - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (3):367-372.
    We discuss the possibility of applying the compactness theorem to the study of finite structures. Given a class of finite structures, it is important to determine whether it can be expressed by a particular category of sentences. We are interested in this type of problem, and use nonstandard method for showing the non‐expressibility of certain classes of finite graphs by an existential monadic second order sentence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henkin constructions of models with size continuum.John T. Baldwin & Michael C. Laskowski - 2019 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 25 (1):1-33.
    We describe techniques for constructing models of size continuum inωsteps by simultaneously building a perfect set of enmeshed countable Henkin sets. Such models have perfect, asymptotically similar subsets. We survey applications involving Borel models, atomic models, two-cardinal transfers and models respecting various closure relations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation