Switch to: References

Citations of:

Science and Human Behavior

New York: Free Press (1963)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How rational is the imagination?Robert J. Sternberg - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6):467-467.
    Byrne has written a terrific book that is, nevertheless, based on a mistaken assumption – that imagination is largely rational. I argue in this commentary that her book follows very well, if one accepts her assumption of rationality, but that the bulk of the evidence available to us contradicts this assumption.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Culture, biology, and human behavior.Horst D. Steklis & Alex Walter - 1991 - Human Nature 2 (2):137-169.
    Social scientists have not integrated relevant knowledge from the biological sciences into their explanations of human behavior. This failure is due to a longstanding antireductionistic bias against the natural sciences, which follows on a commitment to the view that social facts must be explained by social laws. This belief has led many social scientists into the error of reifying abstract analytical constructs into entities that possess powers of agency. It has also led to a false nature-culture dichotomy that effectively undermines (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Behavior change without a theory of learning?Jane Stewart & Joseph Rochford - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unificationism: Philosophy for the modern disunified science of psychology.Arthur W. Staats - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):143-164.
    Abstract Psychology's goal has been to become a science, taking the modern natural sciences as the model. It has not been understood that each science undergoes a transition from early disunification to later unification, that a fundmental dimension is involved that differentiates sciences. Psychology is a modern disunified science, distinguished by its chaotic knowledge and ways of operating. A philosophy of science based on modem unified science, as philosophies generally are, is inappropriate as a means of understanding psychology or of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner's behaviorism implies a subcutaneous homunculus.J. E. R. Staddon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):647.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rule-governed behavior in computational psychology.Edward P. Stabler - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):604-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the process of reinforcement.J. E. R. Staddon - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In the beginning was the word.J. E. R. Staddon - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • B. F. Skinner's theorizing.Douglas Stalker & Paul Ziff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Misinterpreting Mischel.Edmund J. S. Sonuga-Barke - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):693-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bridges from behaviorism to biopsychology.Paul R. Solomon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):498-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensation seeking and the orienting reflex.E. N. Sokolov - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):450-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The conditioned response: More than a knee-jerk in the ontogeny of behavior.William P. Smotherman & Scott R. Robinson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):159-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The homunculus at home.J. David Smith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):697-698.
    In Gray's conjecture, mismatches in the subicular comparator and matches have equal prominence in consciousness. In rival cognitive views novelty and difficulty especially elicit more conscious modes of cognition and higher levels of self-regulation. The mismatch between Gray's conjecture and these views is discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modal knowledge and transmodularity.Leslie Smith - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):729-730.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alternatives to radical behaviorism.Terry L. Smith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):143-144.
    Operant psychologists are looking for alternatives to radical behaviorism. Rachlin offers teleological behaviorism, but it may pose as many difficulties as radical behaviorism. There is, however, a less drastic way to defend Rachlin's thesis of It portrays operant principles as relating distal efficient causes to behavioral effects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A one-sided view of evolution.John Maynard Smith - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):493-493.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The operational analysis of psychological terms.B. F. Skinner - 1945 - Psychological Review 52 (4):270-78.
    The major contributions of operationism have been negative, largely because operationists failed to distinguish logical theories of reference from empirical accounts of language. Behaviorism never finished an adequate formulation of verbal reports and therefore could not convincingly embrace subjective terms. But verbal responses to private stimuli can arise as social products through the contingencies of reinforcement arranged by verbal communities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • The operational analysis of psychological terms.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Signs and countersigns.B. F. Skinner - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some consequences of selection.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):502-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representations and misrepresentations.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reply to Harnad.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):721.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Contingencies and rules.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):607-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coming to terms with private events.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • An operant analysis of problem solving.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):583-591.
    Behavior that solves a problem is distinguished by the fact that it changes another part of the solver's behavior and is strengthened when it does so. Problem solving typically involves the construction of discriminative stimuli. Verbal responses produce especially useful stimuli, because they affect other people. As a culture formulates maxims, laws, grammar, and science, its members behave more effectively without direct or prolonged contact with the contingencies thus formulated. The culture solves problems for its members, and does so by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Behaviorism at fifty.B. F. Skinner - 1974 - New York,: J. Norton Publishers.
    Each of us is uniquely subject to certain kinds of stimulation from a small part of the universe within our skins. Mentalistic psychologies insist that other kinds of events, lacking the physical dimensions of stimuli, are accessible to the owner of the skin within which they occur. One solution often regarded as behavioristic, granting the distinction between public and private events and ruling the latter out of consideration, has not been successful. A science of behavior must face the problem of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Sensation seeking: Exploration of empty spaces or novel stimuli?Edward C. Simmel - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):449-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explaining behavior Skinner's way.Michael A. Simon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):646.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teleological behaviorism and internal control of behavior.Albert Silverstein - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The challenge of representational redescription.Thomas R. Shultz - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):728-729.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Selective observing when the experimenter controls the duration of observing bouts.Richard L. Shull - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):715.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Janus faces of addiction.Peter Shizgal - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):595-596.
    Heyman proposes that external stimuli can promote a switch from a local to a global frame of reference for evaluating the consequences of behavior and that such a change might be critical to breaking the grip of drag addiction. Could incentive stimuli promote a switch in the opposite direction and thus contribute to relapse in the recovered addict?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-control and the panda's thumb.Eliot Shimoff & A. Charles Catania - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):693-693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Molar behaviorism, positivism, and pain.Charles P. Shimp - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):71-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historicism, behaviorism, and the conceptual status of memory representations in animals.Charles P. Shimp - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):389-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Distinguishing between acts and patterns.Eliot Shimoff - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):142-142.
    The costliness of disrupting a pattern may not be a useful criterion for distinguishing between acts and patterns; there are instances in which omitted components of patterns are hard to detect (e.g., typographical errors), or in which distortions are easily introduced (e.g., slurred words in a trite phrase). Are there behavioral criteria for distinguishing between acts and patterns?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Expectancy: The endogenous source of anticipatory activities, including “pseudoconditioned” responses.Patrick J. Sheafor - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):387-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constraints on learning or laws of performance?Sara J. Shettleworth - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more to learning then meeth the eye.Noel E. Sharkey - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):506-507.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pain without behavior: Inhibition of reactions to sensation.Kelly G. Shaver & Jana J. Herrman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):71-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness beyond the comparator.Victor A. Shames & Timothy L. Hubbard - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):697-697.
    Gray's comparator model fails to provide an adequate explanation of consciousness for two reasons. First, it is based on a narrow definition of consciousness that excludes basic phenomenology and active functions of consciousness. Second, match/mismatch decisions can be made without producing an experience of consciousness. The model thus violates the sufficiency criterion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arbitrary effect of consequences yet indispensable?P. Sevenster - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metatheory of animal behavior.Erwin M. Segal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):386-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavioral and cognitive psychology: Mixing the languages of input and output.Evalyn F. Segal - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The interplay between science and theology in uncovering the matrix of human morality.Hans Schwarz - 1993 - Zygon 28 (1):61-75.
    Theology and the life sciences are mutually dependent on one another in the task of understanding the origin and function of moral behavior. The life sciences investigate morality from the perspective of the historical and communal dimension of humanity and point to survival as the primary function of human behavior. A Christian ethic of self‐sacrifice advances the preservation of the entire human and nonhuman creation and should not, therefore, be objected to by the life sciences. Religion, however, is more than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contradiction unresolved.Thomas C. Schelling - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):595-595.
    Extreme sensations – thirst, pain – can focus attention on local consequences at the expense of the overall, perhaps for good evolutionary reasons. Maybe the same phenomenon evolves from prolonged use of addictive substances. The matching law explains mistaken choice, not how a person who has confronted personal catastrophe manages to ignore it in making a locally induced choice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Selectionism, mentalisms, and behaviorism.Jonathan Schull - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):497-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-control: Acts of free will.James A. Schirillo - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):141-141.
    Rachlin overlooks that free will determines when and in what direction acts that appear impulsive will occur. Because behavioral patterns continuously evolve, animals are not guaranteed when they will, or how to, maximize larger-later reinforcements. An animal therefore uses self-control to emit free acts to vary behavioral patterns to optimize larger-later rewards.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Redescribing development.Ellin Kofsky Scholnick - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):727-728.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark