Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Techno-phenomenology: Martin Heidegger and Bruno Latour on how phenomena come to presence.Arianne Conty - 2013 - South African Journal of Philosophy 32 (4):311-326.
    This article will set out to elucidate the ways in which the philosophies of technology of Martin Heidegger and Bruno Latour seek to explain how the phenomenal world of nature, objects and tools come to presence as events through their interrelations with each other and with us. Both thinkers seek to overcome a subject/object divide that they both understand as characterising modernity in order to reveal a greater interdependence between nature and culture, human and machine. Not only do they both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Seinsverständnis and meaning in Heidegger.Rafael Winkler - 2013 - South African Journal of Philosophy 32 (2):149-162.
    This essay presents a defence of the hermeneutical and existential standpoint of Being and Time against Cristina Lafont’s historicist and relativist reading. I show that there are substantive and textual difficulties with the Kantian reading of the understanding of being she endorses, which leads her to ignore the existential and hermeneutical aspects of Heidegger’s theory of meaning. The first section shows that the understanding of being is neither an unrevisable synthetic apriori nor a historically contingent conceptual scheme but that it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phenomenological Problems for the Kairological Reading of Augenblick in Being and Time.Hakhamanesh Zangeneh - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (4):539-561.
    In this paper we examine the key phenomena associated with the notion of kairos in Heidegger’s pre‐Being and Time writings and show that they all fall short of the methodological constraints and conceptual requirements placed on authentic presence in 1927. Though Heidegger’s early studies of Aristotle and the New‐Testament are broadly suggestive of the notion of temporality that is presented in his systematic treatise, none of those earlier texts carry the differentiations within which the Augenblick of Being and Time is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heidegger's topology: Being, place, world, by Jeff Malpas.Roxana Baiasu - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):315-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Phenomenology.Dan Zahavi - manuscript
    In Moran, D. (ed.): Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Routledge, 2008.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Husserl's noema and the internalism‐externalism debate.Dan Zahavi - 2004 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):42-66.
    In a number of papers, Hubert Dreyfus and Ronald McIntyre have claimed that Husserl is an internalist. In this paper, it is argued that their interpretation is based on two questionable assumptions: (1) that Husserl's noema should be interpreted along Fregean lines, and (2) that Husserl's transcendental methodology commits him to some form of methodological solipsism. Both of these assumptions are criticized on the basis of the most recent Husserl-research. It is shown that Husserl's concept of noema can be interpreted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Phenomenology, Ontology, Nihilism: Løgstrup, Levinas, and the Limits of Philosophical Anthropology.Steven Crowell - 2020 - The Monist 103 (1):16-37.
    Despite recent interest in his work, little has been written about Løgstrup’s relation to phenomenology—what he thinks phenomenology is, how it informs his approach to ethics, and what he believes it can accomplish. Here I hope to stimulate further discussion of these matters. In this, consideration of Levinas’s understanding of phenomenology will be useful. While sharing many of Løgstrup’s concerns, Levinas insists on a distinction between phenomenological ontology and “metaphysics,” one that Løgstrup tends to blur in support of his argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and phenomenology.Sebastian Luft - 2018 - In Dan Zahavi (ed.), Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter offers a reassessment of the relationship between Kant, the Kantian tradition, and phenomenology, here focusing mainly on Husserl and Heidegger. Part of this reassessment concerns those philosophers who, during the lives of Husserl and Heidegger, sought to defend an updated version of Kant’s philosophy, the neo-Kantians. The chapter shows where the phenomenologists were able to benefit from some of the insights on the part of Kant and the neo-Kantians, but also clearly points to the differences. The aim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El útil y la cosa. Del mundo del Dasein al mundo como cuadratura.Adrián Bertorello - 2018 - Pensamiento 74 (281):623-637.
    En el presente trabajo se compara la fenomenología del mundo de Sein und Zeit con la reflexión de la cuadratura en la conferencia Das Ding para mostrar cómo el peso de la argumentación en 1927 se centra en el «por mor de» mientras que en 1949 ese peso de desplaza hacia la noción del «donar». Este desplazamiento que saca al útil del contexto del «por mor de» y lo sitúa en otro que no se rige exclusivamente por referencia a una (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Why is Ethics First Philosophy? Levinas in Phenomenological Context.Steven Crowell - 2015 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):564-588.
    This paper explores, from a phenomenological perspective, the conditions necessary for the possession of intentional content, i.e., for being intentionally directed toward the world. It argues that Levinas's concept of ethics as first philosophy makes an important contribution to this task. Intentional directedness, as understood here, is normatively structured. Levinas's ‘ethics’ can be understood as a phenomenological account of how our experience of the other subject as another subject takes place in the recognition of the normative force of a command. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Husserl’s Noetics – Towards a Phenomenological Epistemology.Philipp Berghofer - 2018 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 50 (2):120-138.
    ABSTRACTFor Husserl, noetics is the most fundamental science and the centrepiece of a phenomenological epistemology. Since in his major works Husserl does not develop noetics systematically but uses its main ideas and achievements often in apparent isolation without clarifying their systematic unity, the significance of noetics is often overlooked. Although Husserl has repeatedly stressed the importance of a phenomenological epistemology, what the concrete theses of such an undertaking are supposed to be often remains obscure. We shall see that the best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Phenomenological Naturalism.David Suarez - 2017 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 25 (4):437-453.
    Naturalists seek to ground what exists in a set of fundamental metaphysical principles that they call ‘nature’. But metaphysical principles can’t function as fundamental explanatory grounds, since their ability to explain anything depends on the intelligibility granted by transcendental structures. What makes metaphysical principles intelligible, what unifies them, and allows them to characterize the being of worldly objects are the transcendental structures through which worldly objects are manifest. This means that the search for fundamental explanatory grounds must go deeper than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Positionality and Consciousness in Husserl’s Ideas I.Andrea Staiti - 2016 - Research in Phenomenology 46 (2):277-295.
    _ Source: _Volume 46, Issue 2, pp 277 - 295 In this paper I argue that in Husserl’s _Ideas I_ there is a seeming contradiction between the characterization of pure consciousness as the _residue_ of the performance of the phenomenological reduction and the claim that in the natural attitude consciousness is taken to be an entity is the world. This creates a puzzle regarding the positional status of consciousness in the natural attitude. After reviewing some possible options to solve this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Walking on Two Legs: On The Very Possibility of a Heideggerian Marxism.Ian Angus - 2005 - Human Studies 28 (3):335-352.
    An extended review essay on Andrew Feenberg's Heidegger and Marcuse that argues that the concept of negation in Hegel is distinct from that in Heidegger which makes such an attempted synthesis problematic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Inner Violence of Reason: Re‐reading Heidegger via Education.Vasco D'Agnese - 2015 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 49 (3):435-455.
    Since Plato, Western thought has framed knowing as a method within ‘some realm of what is’ and a predetermined ‘sphere of objects’. The roots and the consequences of this stance towards reason and truth were noted by Heidegger, who equates the history of Western thought with the history of metaphysics. Since Plato, truth has relied on definition, hierarchy and mastery. Discourse on the truth begins to be discourse on the limits of things and, thus, on who is able to set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Why is Ethics First Philosophy? Levinas in Phenomenological Context.Steven Crowell - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):564-588.
    This paper explores, from a phenomenological perspective, the conditions necessary for the possession of intentional content, i.e., for being intentionally directed toward the world. It argues that Levinas's concept of ethics as first philosophy makes an important contribution to this task. Intentional directedness, as understood here, is normatively structured. Levinas's ‘ethics’ can be understood as a phenomenological account of how our experience of the other subject as another subject takes place in the recognition of the normative force of a command. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Heidegger's Descartes and Heidegger's Cartesianism.R. Matthew Shockey - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):285-311.
    Abstract: Heidegger's Sein und Zeit (SZ) is commonly viewed as one of the 20th century's great anti-Cartesian works, usually because of its attack on the epistemology-driven dualism and mentalism of modern philosophy of mind or its apparent effort to ‘de-center the subject’ in order to privilege being or sociality over the individual. Most who stress one or other of these anti-Cartesian aspects of SZ, however, pay little attention to Heidegger's own direct engagement with Descartes, apart from the compressed discussion in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What Can Phenomenology Bring to Ontology?Amie L. Thomasson - 2019 - Res Philosophica 96 (3):289-306.
    “Ontology” is understood and undertaken very differently in the phenomenological tradition than it is in the recent analytic tradition. Here I argue that those differences are not accidental, but instead reflect deeper differences in views about what the proper role and methods for philosophy are. I aim to show that, from a phenomenological perspective, questions about what exists can be answered ‘easily,’ whether through trivial inferences (in the case of ideal abstracta) or (always tentatively, of course) by ordinary empirical means—seeing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Problem of Origin in Husserl’s Phenomenology.Zengding Wu - 2018 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 10 (1):21-34.
    ABSTRACTDuring his philosophical life, Husserl sought to develop his phenomenology as a “science of true beginnings, or origins” that is metaphysically neutral. Nevertheless, according to Heidegger and Derrida, Husserl’s phenomenology remains a kind of metaphysics of presence in that it presupposes a metaphysical notion of “origin”. This paper attempts both to correct Heidegger and Derrida’s misunderstandings of Husserl’s notion of “origin” and to clarify the reason why Husserl’s phenomenology and its pursuit of “origin” is still a metaphysical project.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lacan: the mind of the modernist.Louis A. Sass - 2015 - Continental Philosophy Review 48 (4):409-443.
    This paper offers an intellectual portrait of the French psychoanalyst, Jacques Lacan, by considering his incorporation of perspectives associated with “modernism,” the artistic and intellectual avant-garde of the first half of the twentieth century. These perspectives are largely absent in other alternatives in psychology, psychiatry, and psychoanalysis. Emphasis is placed on Lacan’s affinities with phenomenology, a tradition he criticized and to which he is often seen as opposed. Two general issues are discussed. The first is Lacan’s unparalleled appreciation of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger, Wittgenstein and St Paul on the Last Judgement: On the Roots and Significance of 'The Theoretical Attitude'.Denis McManus - 2013 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (1):143 - 164.
    (2013). Heidegger, Wittgenstein and St Paul on the Last Judgement: On the Roots and Significance of ‘The Theoretical Attitude’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 21, No. 1, pp. 143-164. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2012.686980.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Acerca de los sentidos del mundo en Ser y tiempo.Esteban Lythgoe - 2022 - Revista de Filosofía (Madrid):1-12.
    En Ser y tiempo encontramos posiciones inconsistentes acerca la génesis de la ciencia y la homogeneización del espacio. Sobre la primera es manifiesto el contraste entre un modelo de carácter privativo, caracterizado como un proceso de desmundanización que permite aprender la realidad en su sustancialidad y otro, proyectivo que presenta a la matematización como un modo positivo de tematización. En el presente artículo quisiéramos sostener que estas diferencias estarían asociadas a el hecho de que en esta obra Heidegger opera con (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carleton B. Christensen, Self and World: From Analytic Philosophy to Phenomenology: Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 2008, 394 pp., $137. [REVIEW]Morten S. Thaning - 2010 - Husserl Studies 26 (3):233-243.
    Carleton B. Christensen, Self and World: From Analytic Philosophy to Phenomenology Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s10743-010-9078-2 Authors Morten S. Thaning, Department of Philosophy, Politics, and Management, Copenhagen Business School, Solbjerg Plads 3, 2000 Frederiksberg, Denmark Journal Husserl Studies Online ISSN 1572-8501 Print ISSN 0167-9848 Journal Volume Volume 26 Journal Issue Volume 26, Number 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger's early critique of Husserl.Søren Overgaard - 2003 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 11 (2):157 – 175.
    This paper examines Heidegger's critique of Husserl in its earliest extant formulation, viz. the lecture courses Ontologie from 1923 and Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung from 1923/4. Commentators frequently ignore these lectures, but I try to show that a study of them can reveal both the extent to which Heidegger remains committed to phenomenological research in something like its Husserlian form, and when and why Heidegger must part with Husserl. More specifically, I claim that Heidegger rightly criticizes Husserl's account of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From being to givenness and back: Some remarks on the meaning of transcendental idealism in Kant and Husserl.Sebastian Luft - 2007 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 15 (3):367-394.
    This paper takes a fresh look at a classical theme in philosophical scholarship, the meaning of transcendental idealism, by contrasting Kant's and Husserl's versions of it. I present Kant's transcendental idealism as a theory distinguishing between the world as in-itself and as given to the experiencing human being. This reconstruction provides the backdrop for Husserl's transcendental phenomenology as a brand of transcendental idealism expanding on Kant: through the phenomenological reduction Husserl universalizes Kant's transcendental philosophy to an eidetic science of subjectivity. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Günter Figal's hermeneutics.Theodore George - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):904-912.
    This article offers a survey of some main ideas in Günter Figal's hermeneutics as he presents them in his recent Gegenständlichkeit: Das Hermeneutische und die Philosophie [ Objectivity: The Hermeneutical and Philosophy ]. Figal promises a new approach to the philosophical study of hermeneutics in this work that would advance beyond Gadamer, Heidegger, and others in significant respects. His project opens out from the belief that hermeneutical experience is guided by exteriority; such experience is directed toward and sustained by what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl and the penetrability of the transcendental and mundane spheres.Robert Arp - 2004 - Human Studies 27 (3):221-239.
    There is a two-fold problem the phenomenologist must face: the first has to do with thinking like a phenomenologist given that one is always already steeped in the mundane sphere; the second has to do with the phenomenologist entering into dialogue with those scientists, psychologists, sociologists and other laypersons who still remain in the mundane sphere. I address the first problem by giving an Husserlian-inspired account of the movement from the mundane to the transcendental, and show that there are decent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ruina y recuperación de la vida: La hermenéutica en el joven Heidegger.Carlos Arturo Bedoya Rodas - 2014 - Universitas Philosophica 31 (62).
    El artículo se propone ofrecer un acercamiento a la concepción de filosofía que subyace al proyecto de una hermenéutica de la facticidad elaborado por Martin Heidegger entre 1919-1923. Esta aproximación se lleva a cabo a través del desarrollo que en la constitución de tal proyecto tiene el fenómeno de la ruina. La centralidad que este ocupa en el desarrollo temprano del pensamiento de Heidegger y, particularmente, en el curso del semestre de invierno de 1921/22, que lleva por título Interpretaciones fenomenológicas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heidegger on Expression: Formal Indication and Destruction in the Early Freiburg Lectures.Jonathan O’Rourke - 2018 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 49 (2):109-125.
    Of all the methodological terms used by Heidegger in the early Freiburg period, few have attracted less consensus than Formal Indication. With its relation to the earliest lecture series, critical debate has tended to focus on the extent to which this concept defines the difference between Husserlian and Heideggerian phenomenology. The argument of this paper is that Formal Indication is best understood in its relation to Heidegger’s other key methodological term from this period, Phenomenological Destruction. Not only do both concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rethinking Husserl’s lifeworld: The many faces of the world in Heidegger’s early Freiburg lecture courses.Sebastiano Galanti Grollo - 2022 - Continental Philosophy Review 55 (4):487-502.
    This paper examines the concept of the world elaborated by Heidegger in the early Freiburg lecture courses of the years 1919 to 1923, in which he proposes a renewed conception of phenomenology through a comparison with Husserlian phenomenology. First, I show that although the theme of the lifeworld became central only in late Husserlian works, especially in _The Crisis of European Sciences_, Husserl began to deal with this concept before 1920, anticipating some fundamental issues of the _Crisis_, as it results (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Order, experience, and critique: The phenomenological method in political and legal theory.Sophie Loidolt - 2021 - Continental Philosophy Review 54 (2):153-170.
    The paper investigates phenomenology’s possibilities to describe, reflect and critically analyse political and legal orders. It presents a “toolbox” of methodological reflections, tools and topics, by relating to the classics of the tradition and to the emerging movement of “critical phenomenology,” as well as by touching upon current issues such as experiences of rightlessness, experiences in the digital lifeworld, and experiences of the public sphere. It is argued that phenomenology provides us with a dynamic methodological framework that emphasizes correlational, co-constitutional, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Nature at the Limits of Science and Phenomenology.David Suarez - 2020 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (1):109-133.
    Kant and Heidegger argue that our subjectivity escapes scientific explanation, while also providing the conditions that enable it. This understanding of the relationship between subjectivity and science places limits on the explanatory scope of the sciences. But what makes transcendental reflection on the structure of subjectivity possible in the first place? Fink argues that transcendental philosophy encounters its own limits in attempting to characterize its own conditions of possibility. I argue that the limits of science and transcendental philosophy entail that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • McDowell, Phenomenology and the Awareness of the World.Donnchadh O'Conaill - 2012 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (4):499-518.
    Abstract John McDowell has claimed that the rational link between perceptions and empirical judgements allows us to perceive objects as belonging to a wider reality, one which extends beyond the objects perceived. In this way, we can be said to have a perceptual awareness of the world. I argue that McDowell's account of this perceptual awareness does not succeed. His account as it stands does not have the resources to explain how our perceptions can present objects as belonging to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Meontic and the Militant: On Merleau-Ponty’s Relation to Fink∗.Bryan Smyth - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (5):669-699.
    This paper clarifies the relationship between Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception and Fink’s Sixth Cartesian Meditation with regard to ‘the idea of a transcendental theory of method’. Although Fink’s text played a singularly important role in the development of Merleau-Ponty’s postwar thought, contrary to recent claims made by Ronald Bruzina this influence was not positive. Reconstructing the basic methodological claims of each text, in particular with regard to the being of the phenomenologist, the nature of the productivity that makes phenomenology possible, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Existential Sources of Phenomenology: Heidegger on Formal Indication.Matthew I. Burch - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):258-278.
    : This article contributes to the contemporary debate regarding the young Heidegger’s method of formal indication. Theodore Kisiel argues that this method constitutes a radical break with Husserl---a rejection of phenomenological reflection that paves the way to the non-reflective approach of the Beiträge. Against this view, Steven Crowell argues that formal indication is continuous with Husserlian phenomenology---a refinement of phenomenological reflection that reveals its existential sources. I evaluate this debate and adduce further considerations in favor of Crowell’s view. To do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Steven Crowell: Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger.Inga Römer - 2014 - Husserl Studies 30 (3):283-291.
    In seinem neuen Buch vertieft Steven Crowell seine Auffassung der Phänomenologie als Transzendentalphilosophie, die es mit dem normativen Raum des Sinnes (space of meaning) zu tun habe (vgl. Crowell 2001). Sowohl Husserl als auch Heidegger führen aus seiner Sicht innerhalb der Phänomenologie die kantische Tradition der Transzendentalphilosophie weiter, indem sie der Frage nach den „transzendentalen Bedingungen der Konstitution oder Enthüllung des Sinnes“ (S. 1) nachgehen.Vgl. auch den von Steven Crowell mit herausgegebenen Band Transcendental Heidegger (2007). Da der Sinn aber Crowell (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nasljeđe Heideggerova su-bitka u Lacanovu određenju Drugog.Martina Źeželj - 2014 - Filozofska Istrazivanja 34 (3):377-392.
    U ovome radu istražila sam dosege utjecaja Heideggerove egzistencijalne analitike na Lacanovu psihoanalizu. Pritom sam se naročito usredotočila na utjecaj Heideggerova egzistencijala su-bitka na Lacanovo određenje simboličkog diskursa Drugog. Rad se sastoji od dviju cjelina: u prvoj je izloženo Heideggerovo poimanje su-bitka, a u drugoj Lacanovo određenje registra Simboličkog. Da bi se prispjelo do mogućnosti izlaganja Heideggerova egzistencijala su-bitka i Lacanova diskursa Drugog, nužno je bilo razmotriti osnovne momente tubitkove egzistencije u svijetu i prirodu registra Simboličkog. Usporedba su-bitka i simboličkog (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger Becoming Phenomenological: Interpreting Husserl through Dilthey, 1916–1925. [REVIEW]David C. Abergel - 2020 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (3):313-317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three Difficulties in Phenomenological Discourse: Husserlian Problems and a Heideggerian Solution.Tyler Klaskow - 2018 - Human Studies 41 (1):79-101.
    Phenomenological descriptions are supposed to be revelatory and coincide with the self-showing of the things themselves. These features of phenomenological descriptions lead to the peculiar character of their expression, which has the effect of making them difficult to communicate. That is, the problem with communicating the findings of phenomenological researches is a consequence of the descriptive nature of the endeavor and the disclosive character of phenomenological descriptions. In the Logical Investigations Edmund Husserl recognized that the problem has three facets: how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Eugen Finks Kant-Interpretation.Yusuke Ikeda - 2015 - HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology 4 (2):154-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations