Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)“But it would be wrong”.Stephen Darwall - 2010 - Social Philosophy and Policy 27 (2):135-157.
    Is the fact that an action would be wrong itself a reason not to perform it? Warranted attitude accounts of value suggest about value, that being valuable is not itself a reason but to the reasons for valuing something in which its value consists. Would a warranted attitude account of moral obligation and wrongness, not entail, therefore, that being morally obligatory or wrong gives no reason for action itself? I argue that this is not true. Although warranted attitude theories of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Love and history.Christopher Grau - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (3):246-271.
    In this essay, I argue that a proper understanding of the historicity of love requires an appreciation of the irreplaceability of the beloved. I do this through a consideration of ideas that were first put forward by Robert Kraut in “Love De Re” (1986). I also evaluate Amelie Rorty's criticisms of Kraut's thesis in “The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love is Not Love Which Alters Not When It Alteration Finds” (1986). I argue that Rorty fundamentally misunderstands Kraut's Kripkean analogy, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Escaping the Corset: Rage as a Force of Resistance and Creation in the Korean Feminist Movement.Ji-Yeong Yun - 2022 - Hypatia 37 (2):257-275.
    This article explores rage in the context of Korean feminist movements. Rage as a corporeal force can be combined with other emotional modalities to achieve consistency, durability, efficiency, and intensity. These modalities are interdependent, and rage, in relation to indignation, becomes a revolutionary affect that changes power dynamics. Women's indignant rage challenges the patriarchal value system and increases women's agency. Korean women deploy the politics of rage to “Escape the Corset” and free themselves from the oppressive devices—patriarchal family structures and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The struggle for recognition and the authority of the second person.Thomas Khurana - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):552-561.
    In this introductory paper, I discuss the second-personal approach to ethics and the theory of recognition as two accounts of the fundamental sociality of the human form of life. The first section delineates the deep affinities between the two approaches. They both put a reciprocal social constellation front and center from which they derive the fundamental norms of moral and social life and a social conception of freedom. The second section discusses three points of contrast between the two approaches: The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Recognition, second‐personal authority, and nonideal theory.Stephen Darwall - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):562-574.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 29, Issue 3, Page 562-574, September 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • “You” or “We”: The limits of the second‐person perspective.Axel Honneth - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):581-591.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 29, Issue 3, Page 581-591, September 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Hume on Liberty and Necessity.Godfrey Vesey - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20:111-127.
    David Hume (1711–1776) described the question of liberty and necessity as ‘the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science’ (Hume [1748] 1975, p. 95). He was right about it being contentious. Whether it is metaphysical is another matter. I think that what is genuinely metaphysical is an assumption that Hume, and a good many other philosophers, make in their treatment of the question. The assumption is about language and reality. I call it ‘the conformity assumption’. But more about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Preface.Godfrey Vesey - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20:111-127.
    David Hume (1711–1776) described the question of liberty and necessity as ‘the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science’ (Hume [1748] 1975, p. 95). He was right about it being contentious. Whether it is metaphysical is another matter. I think that what is genuinely metaphysical is an assumption that Hume, and a good many other philosophers, make in their treatment of the question. The assumption is about language and reality. I call it ‘the conformity assumption’. But more about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commentary on Kauffeld.Ralph H. Johnson - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Problem of the First Belief : Group Agents and Responsibility.Onni Hirvonen - 2020 - Journal of Social Ontology 6 (1):1-20.
    Attributing moral responsibility to an agent requires that the agent is a capable member of a moral community. Capable members of a moral community are often thought of as moral reasoners (or moral persons) and, thus, to attribute moral responsibility to collective agents would require showing that they are capable of moral reasoning. It is argued here that those theories that understand collective reasoning and collective moral agency in terms of collective decision-making and commitment – as is arguably the case (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychological consequences of the normativity of moral obligation.Stephen Darwall - 2016 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 43.
    An adequate moral psychology of obligation must bear in mind that although the “sense of obligation” is psychological, what it is a sense of, moral obligation itself, is not. It is irreducibly normative. I argue, therefore, that the “we” whose demands the sense of obligation presupposes must be an ideal rather than an actual “we.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)III-Moral Obligation: Form and Substance.Stephen Darwall - 2010 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110 (1pt1):31-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Behaviorism at fifty.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):615.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Grice without the Cooperative Principle.Fred J. Kauffeld - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reply to Honneth.Stephen Darwall - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):592-596.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 29, Issue 3, Page 592-596, September 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ethical Demand, by K. E. LøgstrupEthical Concepts and Problems, by K. E. Løgstrup.Stephen Darwall - 2017 - Mind 132 (526):558-567.
    Knud Ejler Løgstrup (1905-1981) was a Danish philosopher and theologian of profound significance who deserves to be much better known among anglophone philosoph.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation