Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Explanation Of Behaviour

Humanities Press (1964)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Explanation of Action in History.Constantine Sandis - 2006 - Essays in Philosophy 7 (2):12.
    This paper focuses on two conflations which frequently appear within the philosophy of history and other fields concerned with action explanation. The first of these, which I call the Conflating View of Reasons, states that the reasons for which we perform actions are reasons why (those events which are) our actions occur. The second, more general conflation, which I call the Conflating View of Action Explanation, states that whatever explains why an agent performed a certain action explains why (that event (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism.Alex Rosenberg - 1996 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (1):1-29.
    This review of recent work in the philosophy of science motivated by a commitment to 'naturalism' begins by identifying three key axioms and one theorem shared by philosophers thus self-styled. Owing much to Quine and Ernest Nagel, these philosophers of science share a common agenda with naturalists elsewhere in philosophy. But they have disagreed among themselves about how the axioms and the theorems they share settle long-standing disputes in the philosophy of science. After expounding these disagreements in the work of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Humean motivation and Humean rationality.Mark van Roojen - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 79 (1):37-57.
    Michael Smith's recent defence of the theory shows promise, in that it captures the most common reasons for accepting a Humean view. But, as I will argue, it falls short of vindicating the view. Smith's argument fails, because it ignores the role of rationality conditions on the ascription of motivating reason explanations. Because of these conditions, we must have a theory of rationality before we choose a theory of motivation. Thus, we cannot use Humean restrictions on motivation to argue for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Social and Justified Legal Normativity: Unlocking the Mystery of the Relationship.Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (3):409-433.
    Can Hart's non-cognitivism be reconciled with his rejection of the predictive and sanction-based explanations of law? This paper analyses Hart's notion of the internal point of view and focuses on the notion of acceptance of a rule along the lines of a non-cognitivist understanding of intentional actions. It is argued that a non-cognitivist analysis of acceptance of rules is incomplete and parasitic on a more basic or primary model of acceptance that does not involve mental states. This basic or primary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more than one way to access an image.Lynn C. Robertson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dennett's intentions and Darwin's legacy.Jon Ringen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):386-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • B. F. Skinner's operationism.Jon D. Ringen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Death of the passive subject.Artur Ribeiro - 2018 - History of the Human Sciences 31 (3):105-121.
    In recent years some archaeological commentators have suggested moving away from an exclusively anthropocentric view of social reality. These ideas endorse elevating objects to the same ontological level as humans – thus creating a symmetrical view of reality. However, this symmetry threatens to force us to abandon the human subject and theories of meaning. This article defends a different idea. It is argued here that an archaeology of the social, based on human intentionality, is possible, while maintaining an ontology that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Response classes, operants, and rules in problem solving.Jan G. Rein - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):602-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond the Postmetaphysical Turn: Ethics and Metaphysics in Critical Theory.Craig Reeves - 2016 - Journal of Critical Realism 15 (3):217-244.
    This article explores the relationship between ethics and metaphysics in critical theory through immanent criticism of Fabian Freyenhagen's reconstruction of Adorno. Endorsing Freyenhagen's overall defence of Adorno's position, it argues that several important features of Adorno's position as Freyenhagen interprets it can be made intelligible only on broadly Aristotelian metaphysical presuppositions. These should be thematized explicitly rather than ignored. Moreover, these metaphysical presuppositions are on independent grounds plausible, as recent Aristotelian and critical realist work has indicated, and special difficulties arising (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Questions raised by the reinforcement paradigm.Anatol Rapoport - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):601-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Outflanking the mind-body problem: Scientific progress in the history of psychology.Sam S. Rakover - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (2):145–173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental, yes. Private, no.Howard Rachlin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Is there such a thing as a problem situation?Kjell Raaheim - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality: No mystery.William T. Powers - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Nonreductive materialism and the materialisms of Marx and Heidegger.Douglas V. Porpora - 1982 - Human Studies 5 (1):13 - 30.
    The objective of this paper is to reconsider the relationship between marxism and existential-phenomenological sociology in light of margolis' (1978) recent articulation and systematic defense of what he terms nonreductive materialism--a material monist ontology which acknowledges an irreducible dualism of attributes. it is argued that reductive materialism is philosophically indefensible and that the most important reasons for thinking that marxism entails reductive materialism are mistaken.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic, reference, and mentalism.Ullin T. Place - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality as internality.Don Perlis & Rosalie Hall - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • O que é função? Debates na filosofia da biologia contemporânea.Nei Freitas Nunes-Neto & Charbel Niño El-Hani - 2009 - Scientiae Studia 7 (3):353-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Being Oneself in Another: Recognition and the Culturalist Deformation of Identity.Radu Neculau - 2012 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 55 (2):148-170.
    Abstract Nancy Fraser raises serious doubts about the critical potential of identity theories of recognition on the ground that they encourage the reduction of personal identity to cultural identity. Based on a comparative analysis of Charles Taylor's and Axel Honneth's theories of recognition, this paper argues that Fraser's critique is justified with respect to some aspects of Taylor's theory of identity, but not with respect to his conception of recognition, or to Honneth's conception of both identity and recognition. Taylor's theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A total process approach to perception.Maxine Morphis - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On skinner's radical operationism.J. Moore - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strong evaluation and weak ontology. The predicament of Charles Taylor.Michiel Meijer - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 75 (5):440-459.
    This paper aims to come to grips with the rich philosophy of Charles Taylor by focusing on his concept of ‘strong evaluation’. I argue that a close examination of this term brings out more clearly the continuing tensions in his writings as a whole. I trace back the origin of strong evaluation in Taylor’s earliest writings, and continue by laying out the different philosophical themes that revolve around it. Next, the focus is on the separate arguments in which strong evaluation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Radical behaviorism and mental events: Four methodological queries.Paul E. Meehl - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thomas Reid on moral liberty and common sense.Douglas McDermid - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (2):275 – 303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Telling more than they can know: The positivist account of verbal reports and mental processes.John Mcclure - 1983 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 13 (1):111–128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Epistemological Significance of the Theory of Social Representations.Ivana Marková - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (4):461-487.
    The theory of social representations must be understood in terms of its proper epistemology so that it can accomplish its full potential in social sciences. This is often difficult to achieve because researchers comprehend it in terms of concepts that are part of static and individualistic Newtonian epistemology rather than in terms of dynamic and relational Einsteinian epistemology. This article considers three signposts that Moscovici identifies and analyses in the theory of relativity, namely the relation between epistemology and science, theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cognitive science and the pragmatics of behavior.Lawrence E. Marks - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):150-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Narrative, Myth, and History.Joseph Mali - 1994 - Science in Context 7 (1):121-142.
    The ArgumentDuring the last two decades the debate on the use and abuse of narrative in historiography has taken a new form: ideological instead of methodological. According to poststructuralist critics, the representation of past events and processes in the form of a coherent story turns history into mythology, which is (or serves) conservative ideology. This is so because the fabrication of organic continuity and unity between the past and the present (as well as the future) of society depicts its most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intrinsic versus contrived intentionality.Donald M. MacKay - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Action, causality, and teleology.Ruth Macklin - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 19 (4):301-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The flight from human behavior.C. Fergus Lowe - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The relationship between information theory, statistical mechanics, evolutionary theory, and cognitive Science.Michael Leyton - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethics in psychiatry--the patient's freedom and bondage.E. K. Ledermann - 1982 - Journal of Medical Ethics 8 (4):191-194.
    Ethics is defined as the realm of the 'ought', the realm of conscience which postulates that Man has the freedom to carry out what he judges to be morally right. By such acts he realizes his freedom of making himself into a truer, more authentic person than he was before. A libertarian psychotherapy, based on this ethic, is outlined. Medical science (as all science) belongs to the realm of the 'is' and postulates that the phenomena which it studies follow a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic information: Inference rules + memory.Michael Lebowitz - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interpretation and theory in the natural and the human sciences comments on Kuhn and Taylor.Hugh Lacey - 1990 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 20 (3):197–212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teleology as higher-order causation: A situation-theoretic account.Robert C. Koons - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (4):559-585.
    Situation theory, as developed by Barwise and his collaborators, is used to demonstrate the possibility of defining teleology (and related notions, like that of proper or biological function) in terms of higher order causation, along the lines suggested by Taylor and Wright. This definition avoids the excessive narrowness that results from trying to define teleology in terms of evolutionary history or the effects of natural selection. By legitimating the concept of teleology, this definition also provides promising new avenues for solving (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Problem solving as a cognitive process.Manfred Kochen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):599-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genetic epistemology, history of science and genetic psychology.Richard F. Kitchener - 1985 - Synthese 65 (1):3 - 31.
    Genetic epistemology analyzes the growth of knowledge both in the individual person (genetic psychology) and in the socio-historical realm (the history of science). But what the relationship is between the history of science and genetic psychology remains unclear. The biogenetic law that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny is inadequate as a characterization of the relation. A critical examination of Piaget's Introduction à l'Épistémologie Généntique indicates these are several examples of what I call stage laws common to both areas. Furthermore, there is at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A neglected classic vindicated: The place of George Herbert Mead in the general tradition of semiotics.Erkki Kilpinen - 2002 - Semiotica 2002 (142):1-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Teleology and logical form.Andrew Kernohan - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1):27-34.
    Recent proposals by Taylor, Bennett, Wright and Cohen to identify teleological systems as systems governed by teleological laws and teleological laws as laws of a certain logical form are discussed. Suggested logical forms are treated with both extensional and simple non-extensional models of nomic necessity and shown to generate problematic entailments not derivable from the causal form alone.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social traits, self-observations, and other hypothetical constructs.Douglas T. Kenrick & Richard C. Keefe - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information, causality, and intentionality.David Kelley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):147-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • WHAT IS IMMANENT IN JUDAISM? Transcending A Secular Age. [REVIEW]Martin Kavka - 2012 - Journal of Religious Ethics 40 (1):123-137.
    This essay takes on the implicit claim in Taylor's A Secular Age, forecast in some of his earlier writings, that the desire for a meaningful life can never be satisfied in this life. As a result, A Secular Age is suffused with a tragic view of existence; its love of narratives of religious longing makes no sense otherwise. Yet there are other models of religion that lend meaning to existence, and in the majority of this essay, I take up one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophie analytique de l'action et fondement normatif des sciences de l'homme.J. Nicolas Kaufmann - 1984 - Dialogue 23 (1):3-35.
    La philosophie analytique de l'action se réclame du langage ordinaire de l'action comme une des sources de ses data philosophiques. Elle se propose d'en examiner le fonctionnement, d'en extraire les concepts clés, de caractériser les formes de propositions dans lesquelles s'expriment nos actions et notre façon spontanée de les comprendre, d'examiner l'articulation propre aux stratégies d'action et au discours qui les justifie, et de faire des « proposals » pour la construction d'une théorie de l'action. En somme, il s'agit d'ériger (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can Skinner define a problem?Geir Kaufmann - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):599-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contingencies, rules, and the “problem” of novel behavior.Pere Julià - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to Subpersonal Computational States.José Luis Bermúdez - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (4):333-369.
    Philosophers have often argued that ascriptions of content are appropriate only to the personal level states of folk psychology. Against this, this paper defends the view that the familiar propositional attitudes and states defined over them are part of a larger set of cognitive proceses that do not make constitutive reference to concept possession. It does this by showing that states with nonconceptual content exist both in perceptual experience and in subpersonal information-processing systems. What makes these states content-involving is their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • II. Taylor on the reduction of teleological laws.Joseph Margolis - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):118-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A case study of how a paper containing good ideas, presented by a distinguished scientist, to an appropriate audience, had almost no influence at all.Earl Hunt - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):597-598.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark