Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Albert of saxony.Joél Biard - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Principle of Inertia in the History of Classical Mechanics.Danilo Capecchi - 2024 - Foundations of Science 29 (4):1029-1070.
    Making a history of the principle of inertia, as of any other principle or concept, is a complex but still possible operation. In this work it has been chosen to make a back story which seemed the most natural way for a reconstruction. On the way back, it has been decided to stop at the 6th century CE with the contribution of Ioannes Philoponus. The principle he stated, although very different from the modern one, is certainly associated with it. Going (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Albert of Saxony's View of Complex Terms in Categorical Propositions and the ‘English-Rule’.Michael Joseph Fitzgerald - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (4):347-374.
    The essay first makes some observations on the general interrelationship between the logical writings of Albert and Buridan. Second, it gives an account of a ‘semantic logical model’ for analyzing complex subject terms in some basic categorical propositions which is defended by Albert of Saxony, and briefly recounts Buridan's criticisms of that model. Finally, the essay maintains that the Albertian model is typically compatible with, and a further development of, what is called by a late-fourteenth century anonymous scholar ‘the English-Rule’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Buridan.Jack Zupko - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Descartes on Numerical Identity and Time.John Morrison - 2022 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):230-246.
    According to most contemporary philosophers, the Indiscernibility of Identicals is obviously true. We might therefore expect earlier philosophers to endorse it. But I will use a puzzle about identity over time to argue that Descartes would reject it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Between Square and Hexagon in Oresme’s Livre du Ciel et du Monde.Lorenz Demey - 2019 - History and Philosophy of Logic 41 (1):36-47.
    In logic, Aristotelian diagrams are almost always assumed to be closed under negation, and are thus highly symmetric in nature. In linguistics, by contrast, these diagrams are used to study lexicalization, which is notoriously not closed under negation, thus yielding more asymmetric diagrams. This paper studies the interplay between logical symmetry and linguistic asymmetry in Aristotelian diagrams. I discuss two major symmetric Aristotelian diagrams, viz. the square and the hexagon of opposition, and show how linguistic considerations yield various asymmetric versions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations