Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Binocular vision and image location before Kepler.Robert Goulding - 2018 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 (5):497-546.
    Kepler’s 1604 Optics proposed among many other things a new way of locating the place of the image under reflection or refraction. He rejected the “perspectivist” method that had been used through antiquity and the Middle Ages, whereby the image was located on the perpendicular between the object and the mirror. Kepler faulted the method for requiring a metaphysical commitment to the action of final causes in optics: the notion that the image was at that place because it was best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What is in the Mirror? The Metaphysics of Mirror Images in Albert the Great and Peter Auriol.Lukas Licka - 2019 - In Brian Glenney, José Filipe Silva, Jana Rosker, Susan Blake, Stephen H. Phillips, Katerina Ierodiakonou, Anna Marmodoro, Lukas Licka, Han Thomas Adriaenssen, Chris Meyns, Janet Levin, James Van Cleve, Deborah Boyle, Michael Madary, Josefa Toribio, Gabriele Ferretti, Clare Batty & Mark Paterson (eds.), The Senses and the History of Philosophy. New York, USA: Routledge. pp. 131-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • False reflections.Maarten Steenhagen - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (5):1227-1242.
    Philosophers and psychologists often assume that mirror reflections are optical illusions. According to many authors, what we see in a mirror appears to be behind it. I discuss two strategies to resist this piece of dogma. As I will show, the conviction that mirror reflections are illusions is rooted in a confused conception of the relations between location, direction, and visibility. This conception is unacceptable to those who take seriously the way in which mirrors contribute to our experience of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Experiment and Mathematics: The Study on Lenses according to Giambattista della Porta ’s perspectiva.Fumikazu Saito - 2008 - Circumscribere: International Journal for the History of Science 4 (1):83-101.
    This paper approaches some aspects concerning 16th century optics, particularly, the studies on lenses by Giambattista della Porta in Magiae naturalis libri XX, De refractione optices parte libri novem and De telescopio. An analysis of these works shows that Della Porta sought to explain how lenses work within the traditional theoretical frameworks. Since optics was one of the fields of knowledge that a magician should take into account in his practice, in this paper we point out to the relationship between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Atmospheric Refraction and the Ramus Circle: Aspects of a Late Sixteenth-Century Dispute.Gérald Péoux - 2010 - Annals of Science 67 (4):457-484.
    Summary When dealing with philosophical questions such as the choice of a world system or the substance of heaven, some sixteenth-century astronomers, including Tycho Brahe and Christophe Rothmann, devised more accurate experimental setups so that they could refine their celestial observations. With this desire to listen to nature arose new questions, in particular that of atmospheric refractions, the understanding and resolution of which became decisive to guarantee the best accuracy. However, to solve such practical problems, it was necessary to consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kepler’s optics without hypotheses.Sven Dupré - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):501-525.
    This paper argues that Kepler considered his work in optics as part of natural philosophy and that, consequently, he aimed at change within natural philosophy. Back-to-back with John Schuster’s claim that Descartes’ optics should be considered as a natural philosophical appropriation of innovative results in the tradition of practical and mixed mathematics the central claim of my paper is that Kepler’s theory of optical imagery, developed in his Paralipomena ad Vitellionem (1604), was the result of a move similar to Descartes’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations