Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Roger Swyneshed’s Obligationes: A Logical Game of Inference Recognition?Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2006 - Synthese 151 (1):125 - 153.
    In [Dutilh Novaes, Medieval-obligations as logical Games of Consistency maintenance, synthese, (2004)], I proposed a reconstruction of Walter Burley’s theory of obligationes, based on the idea that Burley’s theory of obligationes could be seen as a logical game of consistency maintenance. In the present paper, I intend to test the game hypothesis on another important theory of obligationes, namely Roger Swyneshed’s theory. In his treatise on obligationes [edited by P.V. Spade, cf. Spade History and philosophy of Logic 3(1982) 1-32], Swyneshed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Medieval Obligationes as Logical Games of Consistency Maintenance.C. Dutilh Novaes - 2005 - Synthese 145 (3):371-395.
    I argue that the medieval form of dialectical disputation known as obligationes can be viewed as a logical game of consistency maintenance. The game has two participants, Opponent and Respondent. Opponent puts forward a proposition P; Respondent must concede, deny or doubt, on the basis of inferential relations between P and previously accepted or denied propositions, or, in case there is none, on the basis of the common set of beliefs. Respondent loses the game if he concedes a contradictory set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Interactive Logic in the Middle Ages.Sara L. Uckelman - 2012 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 21 (4):439-471.
    Recently logic has shifted emphasis from static systems developed for purely theoretical reasons to dynamic systems designed for application to real world situations. The emphasis on the applied aspects of logic and reasoning means that logic has become a pragmatic tool, to be judged against the backdrop of a particular application. This shift in emphasis is, however, not new. A similar shift towards “interactive logic” occurred in the high Middle Ages. We provide a number of different examples of “interactive logic” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Insolubles.Paul Vincent Spade - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)Roger Swyneshed’s Obligationes: A Logical Game of Inference Recognition?Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2006 - Synthese 151 (1):125-153.
    In [Dutilh Novaes, Medieval-obligations as logical Games of Consistency maintenance, synthese, (2004)], I proposed a reconstruction of Walter Burley’s theory of obligationes, based on the idea that Burley’s theory of obligationes could be seen as a logical game of consistency maintenance. In the present paper, I intend to test the game hypothesis on another important theory of obligationes, namely Roger Swyneshed’s theory. In his treatise on obligationes [edited by P.V. Spade, cf. Spade History and philosophy of Logic 3(1982) 1-32], Swyneshed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Disputations, obligations and logical coherence.Mikko Yrjönsuufu - 2000 - Theoria 66 (2):205-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sit Verum Obligationes and Counterfactual Reasoning.Sara L. Uckelman - 2015 - Vivarium 53 (1):90-113.
    In the early 1980s, Paul V. Spade advanced the thesis that obligational reasoning was counterfactual reasoning, based upon his interpretation of the obligationes of Walter Burley, Richard Kilvington, and Roger Swyneshed. Eleonore Stump in a series of contemporary papers argued against Spade’s thesis with respect to Burley and Swyneshed, provisionally admitting it for Kilvington with the caveat that Kilvington’s theory is by no means clear or non-idiosyncratic. In this paper, we revisit the connection between counterfactual reasoning and obligationes, focusing on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paul of Venice on Obligations.Georgette Sinkler - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (3):475-.
    An obligation, in the sense in which it was of interest to medieval logicians from about the early thirteenth century to the end of the scholastic period, is, according to Paul of Venice, a relation limiting one to take some statement affirmatively or negatively. This relation is based on the actions of two individuals: one obligates the other by first putting forward a sentence which the respondent agrees to affirm or deny for a limited time. The sentence the respondent agrees (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Formalizations après la lettre: Studies in Medieval Logic and Semantics.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2006 - Dissertation, Leiden University
    This thesis is on the history and philosophy of logic and semantics. Logic can be described as the ‘science of reasoning’, as it deals primarily with correct patterns of reasoning. However, logic as a discipline has undergone dramatic changes in the last two centuries: while for ancient and medieval philosophers it belonged essentially to the realm of language studies, it has currently become a sub-branch of mathematics. This thesis attempts to establish a dialogue between the modern and the medieval traditions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle'stopics and medieval obligational disputations.Mikko Yrjönsuuri - 1993 - Synthese 96 (1):59 - 82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What Logical Consequence Could, Could Not, Should, and Should Not Be.Sara L. Uckelman - 2024 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 98 (1):255-275.
    In ‘Logical Consequence (Slight Return)’, Gillian Russell asks ‘What is logical consequence?’, a question which has vexed logicians since at least the twelfth century, when people first began to wonder what it meant for one sentence (or proposition) to follow from another sentence (or proposition, or set of sentences, or set of propositions), or whether it was possible to put down rules determining when the relation of ‘follows from’ (or ‘is antecedent to’) holds. Her aim is threefold: (1) to explain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark