Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Completeness and categoricity: Frege, gödel and model theory.Stephen Read - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):79-93.
    Frege’s project has been characterized as an attempt to formulate a complete system of logic adequate to characterize mathematical theories such as arithmetic and set theory. As such, it was seen to fail by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem of 1931. It is argued, however, that this is to impose a later interpretation on the word ‘complete’ it is clear from Dedekind’s writings that at least as good as interpretation of completeness is categoricity. Whereas few interesting first-order mathematical theories are categorical or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On the calculus ratiocinator.J. W. Swanson - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):315 – 331.
    The project, entertained by Leibniz and others, of creating an ideal language to facilitate ratiocination, is investigated in detail. Six possible relations between the ideal language (IL) and the natural language (NL) it replaces are studied. (1) IL says exactly what NL says, but says it much more clearly. (2) IL says exactly what NL says, but does so more economically. (3) IL says exactly what NL says, but does so more succinctly. (4) IL says part of what NL says, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptualism, ramified logic, and nominalized predicates.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 1986 - Topoi 5 (1):75-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Structuralism and representation theorems.George Weaver - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3):257-271.
    Much of the inspiration for structuralist approaches to mathematics can be found in the late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century program of characterizing various mathematical systems upto isomorphism. From the perspective of this program, differences between isomorphic systems are irrelevant. It is argued that a different view of the import of the differences between isomorphic systems can be obtained from the perspective of contemporary discussions of representation theorems and that from this perspective both the identification of isomorphic systems and the reduction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A formalization of a nominalistic set theory.C. Chihara, Y. Lin & T. Schaffter - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (2):155 - 169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Developing arithmetic in set theory without infinity: some historical remarks.Charles Parsons - 1987 - History and Philosophy of Logic 8 (2):201-213.
    In this paper some of the history of the development of arithmetic in set theory is traced, particularly with reference to the problem of avoiding the assumption of an infinite set. Although the standard method of singling out a sequence of sets to be the natural numbers goes back to Zermelo, its development was more tortuous than is generally believed. We consider the development in the light of three desiderata for a solution and argue that they can probably not all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mathematical instrumentalism meets the conjunction objection.Hawthorne James - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (4):363-397.
    Scientific realists often appeal to some version of the conjunction objection to argue that scientific instrumentalism fails to do justice to the full empirical import of scientific theories. Whereas the conjunction objection provides a powerful critique of scientific instrumentalism, I will show that mathematical instnrunentalism escapes the conjunction objection unscathed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Remarks on a survey article on many valued logic by A. Urquhart.Andrzej Wroński - 1987 - Studia Logica 46 (3):275 - 278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On a complexity-based way of constructivizing the recursive functions.F. W. Kroon & W. A. Burkhard - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (1):133 - 149.
    Let g E(m, n)=o mean that n is the Gödel-number of the shortest derivation from E of an equation of the form (m)=k. Hao Wang suggests that the condition for general recursiveness mn(g E(m, n)=o) can be proved constructively if one can find a speedfunction s s, with s(m) bounding the number of steps for getting a value of (m), such that mn s(m) s.t. g E(m, n)=o. This idea, he thinks, yields a constructivist notion of an effectively computable function, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Semantics of the Constructible Levels.George Boolos - 1970 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 16 (2):139-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logique mathématique et philosophie des mathématiques.Yvon Gauthier - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):243-275.
    Pour le philosophe intéressé aux structures et aux fondements du savoir théorétique, à la constitution d'une « méta-théorétique «, θεωρíα., qui, mieux que les « Wissenschaftslehre » fichtéenne ou husserlienne et par-delà les débris de la métaphysique, veut dans une intention nouvelle faire la synthèse du « théorétique », la logique mathématique se révèle un objet privilégié.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Set Theoretic Approach to the Simple Theory of Types.Michael D. Resnik - 1969 - Theoria 35 (3):239-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On maximum logical candor and extensionality.R. M. Martin - 1963 - Synthese 15 (1):283 - 291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functions computable by a computer.A. Schurmann - 1971 - Studia Logica 27 (1):57 - 72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark