Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Defending and Defining Environmental Responsibilities for the Health Research Sector.Bridget Pratt - 2024 - Science and Engineering Ethics 30 (3):1-21.
    Six planetary boundaries have already been exceeded, including climate change, loss of biodiversity, chemical pollution, and land-system change. The health research sector contributes to the environmental crisis we are facing, though to a lesser extent than healthcare or agriculture sectors. It could take steps to reduce its environmental impact but generally has not done so, even as the planetary emergency worsens. So far, the normative case for why the health research sector should rectify that failure has not been made. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against the Equality of Moral Spheres in Healthcare.Jonathan Herington & Lainie Friedman Ross - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (12):23-25.
    In a recent paper, Doernberg and Truog identify that physicians must routinely navigate a set of distinct “moral spheres”—clinical care, research, population health and the market.1 While the conce...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • For the Common Good: Philosophical Foundations of Research Ethics.Alex John London - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    The foundations of research ethics are riven with fault lines emanating from a fear that if research is too closely connected to weighty social purposes an imperative to advance the common good through research will justify abrogating the rights and welfare of study participants. The result is an impoverished conception of the nature of research, an incomplete focus on actors who bear important moral responsibilities, and a system of ethics and oversight highly attuned to the dangers of research but largely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Social Risks of Science.Jonathan Herington & Scott Tanona - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (6):27-38.
    Many instances of scientific research impose risks, not just on participants and scientists but also on third parties. This class of social risks unifies a range of problems previously treated as distinct phenomena, including so-called bystander risks, biosafety concerns arising from gain-of-function research, the misuse of the results of dual-use research, and the harm caused by inductive risks. The standard approach to these problems has been to extend two familiar principles from human subjects research regulations—a favorable risk-benefit ratio and informed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Redistributing Fair Subject Selection.Kirstin Borgerson - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):25-27.
    Volume 20, Issue 2, February 2020, Page 25-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Need for Non-Ideal Theory: A Case Study in Deliberative Democracy.Danielle Wenner - 2017 - In Kevin Vallier & Michael Weber (eds.), Political Utopias: Contemporary Debates. New York, NY: Oup Usa. pp. 203-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Do Surgical Trials Meet the Scientific Standards for Clinical Trials.Danielle M. Wenner, Baruch A. Brody, Anna Jarman, Jacob M. Kolman, Nelda Wray & Carol Ashton - 2012 - Journal of the American College of Surgeons 215 (5):722-730.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Difficulties with Applying a Strong Social Value Requirement to Clinical Research.David B. Resnik - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (6):35-37.
    In an insightful article published in this issue of the Hastings Center Report, Danielle Wenner criticizes what she describes as transactional approaches to the social value requirement in clinical research and defends a “basic structure approach.” Transactional approaches understand social value obligations as arising from transactions (or relationships) between research subjects, investigators, sponsors, and other parties. The basic structure approach, by contrast, understands social value obligations as stemming from the demands of Rawlsian social justice. According to Wenner, “The primary justification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Social Value Misconception in Clinical Research.Jake Earl, Liza Dawson & Annette Rid - forthcoming - American Journal of Bioethics.
    Clinical researchers should help respect the autonomy and promote the well-being of prospective study participants by helping them make voluntary, informed decisions about enrollment. However, participants often exhibit poor understanding of important information about clinical research. Bioethicists have given special attention to “misconceptions” about clinical research that can compromise participants’ decision-making, most notably the “therapeutic misconception.” These misconceptions typically involve false beliefs about a study’s purpose, or risks or potential benefits for participants. In this article, we describe a misconception involving (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context is Needed When Assessing Fair Subject Selection.G. Owen Schaefer - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):20-22.
    Volume 20, Issue 2, February 2020, Page 20-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Locating the Source(s) of the Social Value Requirement(s).David Wendler - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (6):33-35.
    In this issue of the Hastings Center Report, Danielle Wenner looks at a few prominent analyses of the social value requirement for clinical research, claiming that they are all based on what she calls a transactional model of research ethics. She argues that the transactional model fails to provide a secure foundation for the social value requirement, and then, appealing to John Rawls, she argues that a more secure foundation lies in the principles of social justice. Wenner's attempt to locate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Competing Duties and Professional Roles.Rosamond Rhodes - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (12):25-28.
    I heartily agree with Sam Doernberg and Robert Troug’s claims that there are important differences between “general morality” and medical ethics, and that in some instances they issue contradictory...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fair Inclusion and the Pursuit of Robustly Generalizable Clinically Relevant Knowledge.Ana S. Iltis - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):27-30.
    Volume 20, Issue 2, February 2020, Page 27-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shining a Light also Casts a Shadow: Neuroimaging Incidental Findings in Neuromarketing Research.Owen M. Bradfield - 2021 - Neuroethics 14 (3):459-465.
    Rapid growth in structural and functional brain research has led to increasing ethical discussion of what to do about incidental findings within the brains of healthy neuroimaging research participants that have potential health importance, but which are beyond the original aims of the study. This dilemma has been widely debated with respect to general neuroimaging research but has attracted little attention in the context of neuromarketing studies. In this paper, I argue that neuromarketing researchers owe participants the same ethical obligations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations