Switch to: References

Citations of:

Ethics and Action

Religious Studies 9 (2):245-247 (1972)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Dorothea and Casaubon.Olli Lagerspetz - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (260):211 - 232.
    Dorothea, an idealistic young lady, is the central figure of George Eliot's Middlemarch . She longs to devote her life to something valuable, looking up to people like St Teresa as her ideal. Contrary to all expectations, she decides to marry Casaubon, an elderly clergyman. For years, Casaubon has been preparing his magnum opus called ‘Key to All Religions’. In the milieu where Dorothea is living—a quiet English parish in the 1830s—Casaubon's scholarly project appears to her as the right object (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Common sense and common convictions: Sociology as a science, phenomenological sociology and the hermeneutical point of view. [REVIEW]Dieter Misgeld - 1983 - Human Studies 6 (1):109 - 139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Politics and 'the fragility of the ethico-cultural'.Peter Lassman - 2000 - History of the Human Sciences 13 (1):125-139.
    This article takes up Peter Winch’s remarks concerning ‘the “fragility” of the conditions under which ethical conceptions can be active in social life’. It explores Winch’s discussion of political concepts and his account of the nature of politics. There are two related themes: a concern with the nature of political concepts; and a recognition (a reminder?) of the way in which disagreement belongs to our idea of politics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Peter Winch on ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Socratic’ Reasoning.Olli Lagerspetz - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (2):146-162.
    Peter Winch often returned to questions about the nature of logic. In the context of his work on Wittgenstein and political philosophy in the 1990s, Winch described a contrast between ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Socratic’ reasoning. Aristotelian conceptions of reasoning, attributed to Frege and Russell, would see logic as a formal science and rationality as consistency with pre‐existent rules of inference. The Socratic conception, attributed to Wittgenstein, understands rational argument as a form of socially embedded dialogue that involves moral relationships and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Investigating “man’s relation to reality”: Peter Winch, the vanishing shed and metaphysics after Wittgenstein.Olli Lagerspetz - 2023 - Philosophical Investigations 47 (1):3-23.
    Peter Winch believed that the central task of philosophy was to investigate ‘the force of the concept of reality’ in human practices. This involved creative dialogue with critical metaphysics. In ‘Ceasing to Exist’, Winch considered what it means to judge that something unheard-of has happened. Referring to Wittgenstein, Winch argued that judgments concerning reality must relate our observations to a shared ‘flow of life’. This implies criticism of the form of epistemology associated with metaphysical realism. Just as, according to Wittgenstein, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Investigating “man’s relation to reality”: Peter Winch, the vanishing shed and metaphysics after Wittgenstein.Olli Lagerspetz - 2023 - Philosophical Investigations 47 (1):3-23.
    Peter Winch believed that the central task of philosophy was to investigate ‘the force of the concept of reality’ in human practices. This involved creative dialogue with critical metaphysics. In ‘Ceasing to Exist’, Winch considered what it means to judge that something unheard-of has happened. Referring to Wittgenstein, Winch argued that judgments concerning reality must relate our observations to a shared ‘flow of life’. This implies criticism of the form of epistemology associated with metaphysical realism. Just as, according to Wittgenstein, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The commitment in feeling absolutely safe.Hermen Kroesbergen - 2018 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 84 (2):185-203.
    The experience of feeling safe even in the midst of trials and temptations seems to be a central feature of the Christian faith. In this article I will try to solve some possible difficulties in understanding this kind of absolute safety by discussing some problems noted by philosophers in connection with the related statements by Socrates that a good man cannot be harmed, and by Wittgenstein that he sometimes feels absolutely safe, that nothing can injure him whatever happens. First, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Personal Love of the Good.Camilla Kronqvist - 2019 - Philosophia 47 (4):977-994.
    In order to articulate an account of erotic love that does not attempt to transcend its personal features, Robert Solomon and Martha Nussbaum lean on the speeches by Aristophanes and Alcibiades in Plato’s Symposium. This leads them to downplay the sense in which love is not only for another person, but also for the good. Drawing on a distinction between relative and absolute senses of speaking about the good, I mediate between two features of love that at first may seem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fear and Reason.John Kekes - 2013 - Philosophy 88 (4):555-574.
    The subject of this paper is a particular kind of fear. The danger to which it is a response is the possibility that the evaluative dimension of life from which we derive the values by which we live is arbitrary. If it were arbitrary, nothing we value would be valuable. There are strong reasons both for and against this kind of fear. I am concerned with understanding these reasons and judging their strengths and weaknesses.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language, moral order and political praxis.Lena Jayyusi - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (1):75-93.
    The paper argues that the debate between objectivist criticism and postmodern critique represents a fracturing of the modes of mundane social and linguistic practice. The two together miss the open-textured character of language-in-use and the reflexive properties of situated human practice. Both difference and agreement are grounded in the multiplicity of criteria that are a feature of the logical grammar of language, and therefore of everyday praxis, including that of critique. To escape the duality of foundationalism on the one hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relativism, reality and philosophy.John Horton - 2000 - History of the Human Sciences 13 (1):19-36.
    This article explores Peter Winch’s account of the relationship between language and reality. It defends Winch against some common misunderstandings of his views but identifies two problematic areas. The first concerns the internal coherence of his account of philosophy. The second relates to the issue of rejecting particular ways of life or cultural practices as erroneous or illusory. One source of these problems is a tension between Winch’s official conception of philosophy and his own commitment to ‘defending’ the plurality of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Case for Moral History – Universality and Change in Ethics after Wittgenstein.Nora Hämäläinen - 2020 - Philosophical Investigations 43 (4):363-381.
    Philosophical Investigations, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exemplarity Between Tradition and Critique.Jennifer A. Herdt - 2019 - Journal of Religious Ethics 47 (3):552-565.
    Moral exemplarism, which insists on the centrality of particular embodiments of exemplary virtue to the moral life, is currently receiving significant attention within moral philosophy as well as theological and religious ethics. This introductory essay situates the contributions made by this focus issue on moral exemplarity in relation to the history of attention to moral exemplars, the twentieth‐century turn to virtue, philosopher Linda Zagzebski’s exemplarist moral theory, Stanley Hauerwas’s particularist embrace of Christian discipleship, Foucauldian turns to critique and self‐cultivation, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Croyance, compréhension et incompréhension : Wittgenstein et la religion.Cora Diamond - 2011 - ThéoRèmes 1 (1).
    Wittgenstein avait, pourrait-on dire, une « sensibilité religieuse ». Dans un essai vaste et perspicace sur Wittgenstein et la religion, Peter Winch a décrit l’attitude de Wittgenstein à l’égard de la vie ainsi que son regard sur sa propre vie d’une façon qui met en lumière leur caractère religieux [Winch 1994, p. 109-110]. Mais il n’est pas aisé de voir clairement quelles furent les opinions de Wittgenstein au sujet de la religion et de la croyance religieuse, opinions qui, de fait, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Moral Incapacity.Craig Taylor - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (272):273 - 285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Calling Solomon’s Bluff: Ethics, Aspect‐Perception and the Unity of the Tractatus.Michael Campbell - 2020 - Philosophical Investigations 43 (3):223-253.
    In this paper, I consider how we ought to read the aspect‐perception passages in the Tractatus Logico‐Philosophicus (TLP) in the light of its ethics. I engage with a recent proposal, of Genia Schönbaumsfeld's, that we should replace the TLP account of aspect‐perception with that which Wittgenstein puts forward in the Philosophical Investigations (PI). I show that, far from helping us to grasp the ethical vision contained in the TLP, this proposal obscures it. I go on to draw some conclusions from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Peter Winch: “Unity: Presupposition or Demand?”.Steven Burns - 2020 - Philosophical Investigations 44 (2):109-118.
    Philosophical Investigations, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral Sanity or ‘Who Killed Boy Staunton’.Steven Burns - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (sup1):227-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Davidson and a Twist of Wittgenstein: Metaontology, Self-Canceling Paradox, and Settled Insight.Jeremy Barris - 2018 - Philosophia 46 (2):255-274.
    The paper proposes with Davidson that the talk of metaontology is literally meaningless, but with Wittgenstein that it is so in a way that grants a unique type of insight. More specifically, it argues both that Davidson’s arguments have a cogency that is hard to dismiss, and also that, since his own arguments are metaontological, they are self-referential, and consequently in turn undermine their own meaning as well. The paper argues further that metaontological statements cannot be avoided. Consequently, this kind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Moral tragedy.Peter Drum - 2014 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 4 (1):155-160.
    Polemizując z poglądami niektórych filozofów moralności, autor broni tezy, iż jednoznacznie dobrzy ludzie mogą być pewni spokoju swej duszy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark