Switch to: References

Citations of:

On violence

Journal of Philosophy 66 (19):601-616 (1969)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (2 other versions)The idea of violence.C. A. J. Coady - 1985 - Philosophical Papers 14 (1):3-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Reconstructing the groundwork.Marcus G. Singer - 1982 - Ethics 93 (3):566-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Anabaptist two kingdom dualism: metaphysical grounding for non-violence.Caleb Zimmerman - 2021 - Religious Studies:598-609.
    A non-violent position drawn from the Anabaptist tradition (‘two-kingdom dualism’) is contrasted with the Christian pacifism with which that position is commonly conflated. It is argued that two-kingdom dualism more effectively leverages the philosophical and practical features of its particularly Christian character than does Christian pacifism – and that these features may have implications beyond the philosophy of religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Violence in schools: zero tolerance policies.Zdenko Kodelja - 2019 - Ethics and Education 14 (2):247-257.
    ABSTRACTThere is a wide consensus that violence in schools is something so morally wrong that it must not be tolerated. Therefore, the intolerance shown by a teacher towards students’ violent behaviour in school could be understood as a virtue and his moral obligation and legal duty. On the other hand, extreme toleration towards an evil such as violence becomes a vice, for example, when a teacher makes it possible for an innocent student to become a victim of other students’ physical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Just War, Cyber War, and the Concept of Violence.Christopher J. Finlay - 2018 - Philosophy and Technology 31 (3):357-377.
    Recent debate on the relationship between cyber threats, on the one hand, and both strategy and ethics on the other focus on the extent to which ‘cyber war’ is possible, both as a conceptual question and an empirical one. Whether it can is an important question for just war theorists. From this perspective, it is necessary to evaluate cyber measures both as a means of responding to threats and as a possible just cause for using armed kinetic force. In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Between mediation and critique: Quaker nonviolence in apartheid Cape Town, 1976–1990.Mtc Shafer - 2017 - European Journal of Political Theory 19 (4):593-613.
    In the final years of legal apartheid, the small community of Quakers in Cape Town, South Africa sought to apply their tradition of political and theological nonviolence to the systematic injustice...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On justifying violence.Kai Nielsen - 1981 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):21 – 57.
    I discuss the justification of political violence even within democracies. I define ?violence? and indicate how its evaluative force sometimes has conceptually distorting effects. Though acts of violence are at least prima facie wrong, circumstances can arise where, even in democracies, some of them are morally justified. To establish this, three paradigm cases of non?revolutionary political violence are examined. The question is then discussed whether revolutionary violence is ever justified as a means of establishing or promoting human freedom and happiness. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wolff on violence.Patrick Flanagan - 1972 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):271 – 278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Trust and Contingency Plans.Lee-Ann Chae - 2022 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 52 (7):689-699.
    Trusting relationships are both valuable and risky. Where the risks are high and the fears of betrayal are also high, it might seem rational to try to mitigate the risks, while still enjoying the benefits of the trusting relationship, by forming a contingency plan. A contingency plan—in the sense I am interested in—involves contingent punishments for defection, which are primarily meant to encourage the trusted partner to act trustworthily. I argue, however, that such contingency plans suffer from an internal tension (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the concept of violence coherent?Andrew Prior - 1972 - Philosophical Papers 1 (2):82-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nothing sacred.Stathis Gourgouris - 2024 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    Enlightenment thought is widely considered to consist of four key features--atheism, democracy, humanism, and modernity. Common to all is an explicit process of desacralization. Yet the intellectual history of these concepts reveals that in the process of desacralization new sacred spaces arose in their name. The aim of Nothing Sacred is to question this second-order sacralization and consider, in a form of negative dialectics, whether (and how) these domains can argue against themselves in order to once again desacralize their own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)The idea of violence.C. A. J. Coady - 1985 - Philosophical Papers 14 (1):1-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Idea of Violence.C. A. J. Coady - 1986 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (1):3-19.
    ABSTRACT Violence is a central idea for political theory but there is very little agreement about how it should be understood. This paper examines some fashionable approaches to the concept and argues against ‘wide’ definitions, particularly those of the ‘structuralist’ variety of which that offered by the sociologist, Johan Galtung, is taken as typical. A critique is also given of ‘legitimist’ definitions which incorporate some strong notion of illegitimacy into the very meaning of violence. Structuralist definitions are much favoured by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Kantian Autonomy and Divine Commands.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 1987 - Faith and Philosophy 4 (3):276-281.
    James Rachels has argued that a morally autonomous person (in Kant’s sense) could not consistently accept the authority of divine commands. Against Rachels, this essay argues (a) that the Kantian concept of moral autonomy is to be analyzed in terms of an agent’sresponsiveness to the best available moral reasons and (b) that it is simply question-begging against divine command theory to assume that such commands could not count as the best moral reasons available to an agent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Violence and Silencing: A Philosophical Investigation of Apartheid.Jacqui Poltera - 2011 - Critical Horizons 12 (2):232-250.
    With reference to examples of violence during Apartheid, I argue that the socio-political contexts in which violence occurs significantly shape agents ideas about and responses to violence. As such, philosophers can only make sense of why perpetrators and bystanders alike may have judged violent acts morally justifiable or failed to challenge instances of violence against the backdrop of the particular characteristics of the socio-political context in which it occurs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark