Dissertation, İstanbul Bilgi University (
2024)
Copy
BIBTEX
Abstract
In the Third Antinomy of the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) [Kritik der reinen
Vernunft], Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) associates freedom with infinity. According to
the definition given in this book, only an infinite being not subject to causality can be
defined as free. However, the fact that a finite being, such as a human, is always subject
to the laws of nature implies that they are perpetually bound by causality, which hinders
their freedom. Freedom devoid of causality cannot be theoretically justified. Another
reason for this is Kant’s assertion in the Second Analogy of Critique of Pure Reason,
where he states that everything in the phenomenal world is subject to causality.
Accordingly, freedom can be conceived not in the phenomenal world but only in the
noumenal world.
In the First Critique, freedom, defined as a cause without a cause, a cause without being
the result of another cause, later be characterized as negative freedom in the third
section of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785) [Grundlegung zur
Metaphysik der Sitten]. Such conceptualization of freedom cannot be determined by
any other cause than itself. While there may be a theoretical foundation for accepting
such a cause as uncaused, we have moral reasons to believe in it. This moral foundation
in question guides us toward the notion of positive freedom. Here, unlike negative
freedom, we are subject to moral laws, and as long as we comply with these, we can
experience freedom as a finite being. This is because adhering to the laws we set for
ourselves enables us to be morally the cause of our own actions. Thus, Kant renders
freedom through positive freedom. Following this line of argument, negative freedom
appears meaningful to us only within the framework of positive freedom.
Jean-Luc Nancy (1940-2021) finds a problematic Kantian account of freedom as an
uncaused cause in his book The Experience of Freedom (1988) [L’expérience de la
liberté]. Because, according to this perspective, humans are not only subject to the laws
of nature but also to moral cause-and-effect relationships with others, they exist at the
ix
limit of freedom. By this means, considering freedom as a duty imposed on the subject
leads to ambiguous analyses such as negative/positive freedom in Kantian
philosophyーIn post-Kantian philosophy, the ambiguity persists until Friedrich
Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854)1
, who finds the solution by negating freedom.
Therefore, according to Nancy, freedom should be considered not as a Kantian Idea
but through its relationship with human finitude and experience. Thus, through the
criticism directed at Kant in Martin Heidegger’s (1889-1976) Kant and the Problem of
Metaphysics (1929) [Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik], Nancy attempts to
resolve the confusion created by the concept of freedom, which despite being
associated with infinity in Kant, is made possible in the practical world through respect
for the moral law. In this direction, Nancy finds the solution in the freedom that
becomes conceptually elusive, transforming it into an act that goes beyond being a
mere duty and which permeates all our experiences.
In this book, Nancy introduces the initial stages of “community” and “singularity”
concepts, which he would later develop further. For this, he begins the book's
introductory section by emphasizing Martin Heidegger’s statement in §9 of Being and
Time (1927) [Sein und Zeit], where “freedom” is mentioned as another name for
existence. As a justification, he refers to the concept of Da-sein [being-there] and states
that every being [être] is a being-in-common [être-en-commun], and freedom should
be thought of through this. Namely, the problem of freedom is approached not as a
political or ethical issue but as an ontological matter. Within the framework of beingin-common, this situation transforms into an ontological “generosity [générosité
ontologique].”
1 Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom [Philosophische Untersuchungen
über das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit und die damit zusammenhängenden Gegenstände], Schelling,
approaches freedom not through infinity but rather through finitude. While Heidegger and Nancy pursue
different paths, they both adhere to the idea of finitude freedom in Schelling.
x
Despite primarily emphasizing Heidegger’s thought in writing this text as his
aggrégation thesis, Jean-Luc Nancy desires to transcend it and maintain a certain
distance. This transcendence and distancing include authors from the French
Phenomenological tradition, such as Georges Bataille (1897-1962), Maurice Blanchot
(1907-2003), and Jean-François Lyotard (1924-1998), and also incorporate the
emphasis from Hannah Arendt (1906-1975) that death cannot be thought of
independently of life. Referencing many philosophers from the continental philosophy
tradition and developing a thematic reading through freedom, this bookーlike Nancy’s
other worksーseeks ways to experience philosophy and thought freely in this own
writing experience. So much so that this book, unlike Nancy’s other works like The
Inoperative Community (1986) [La communauté désoeuvrée] ve Being Singular Plural
(1996) [Être Singulier Pluriel], which is not widely discussed in secondary sources, is
challenging to follow. Therefore, in examining this book as my Master’s research thesis
and addressing the idea of freedom in Nancy, I found it appropriate to adopt a close
reading method. Certainly, this research should not be considered independent of works
such as The Discourse of Syncope (1976) [Le discours de la syncope], The Categorical
Imperative (1983) [L’impératif catégorique], as they serve as examples of while
engaging in philosophy, how Nancy refers and relates to the works within the
philosophical tradition.