Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Substitutivity.Scott Soames - 1987 - In Judith Jarvis Thomson (ed.), On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright. MIT Press. pp. 99-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Reference and proper names.Tyler Burge - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (14):425-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • Proper names as predicates.Steven E. Boër - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 27 (6):389 - 400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Situations and attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (11):668-691.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   585 citations  
  • Situations and Attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1983 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Edited by John Perry.
    This volume tackles the slippery subject of 'meaning'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   410 citations  
  • Situations and Attitudes.Jerry Butterfield - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (143):292-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Generalized quantifiers and natural language.John Barwise & Robin Cooper - 1981 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2):159--219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   599 citations  
  • Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Language.Jon Barwise - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4:159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • What's in a name.Kent Bach - 1981 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):371 – 386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Standardization vs. conventionalization.Kent Bach - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (6):677 - 686.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description.Bertrand Russell - 1918 - In Mysticism and logic. Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. pp. 152-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   286 citations  
  • Frege’s Puzzle (2nd edition).Nathan U. Salmon - 1986 - Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
    This is the 1991 (2nd) edition of the 1986 book (MIT Press), considered to be the classic defense of Millianism. The nature of the information content of declarative sentences is a central topic in the philosophy of language. The natural view that a sentence like "John loves Mary" contains information in which two individuals occur as constituents is termed the naive theory, and is one that has been abandoned by most contemporary scholars. This theory was refuted originally by philosopher Gottlob (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • On sense and reference.Gottlob Frege - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge. pp. 36--56.
    Equality1 gives rise to challenging questions which are not altogether easy to answer. Is it a relation? A relation between objects, or between names or signs of objects? In my Begriffsschrift I assumed the latter. The reasons which seem to favour this are the following: a = a and a = b are obviously statements of differing cognitive value; a = a holds a priori and, according to Kant, is to be labeled analytic, while statements of the form a = (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   425 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Gareth Evans - 1982 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by John Henry McDowell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1957 citations  
  • Two theories of names.Gabriel Segal - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (5):547–563.
    Two semantic theories of proper names are explained and assessed. The theories are Burge’s treatment of proper names as complex demonstratives and Larson and Segal’s quasi-descriptivist account of names. The two theories are evaluated for empirical plausibility. Data from deficits, processing models, developmental studies and syntax are all discussed. It is concluded that neither theory is fully confirmed or refuted by the data, but that Larson and Segal’s theory has more empirical plausibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Articulated terms.Mark Richard - 1993 - Philosophical Perspectives 7:207-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The indexical character of names.M. Pelczar & J. Rainsbury - 1998 - Synthese 114 (2):293-317.
    Indexicals are unique among expressions in that they depend for their literal content upon extra-semantic features of the contexts in which they are uttered. Taking this peculiarity of indexicals into account yields solutions to variants of Frege's Puzzle involving objects of attitude-bearing of an indexical nature. If names are indexicals, then the classical versions of Frege's Puzzle can be solved in the same way. Taking names to be indexicals also yields solutions to tougher, more recently-discovered puzzles such as Kripke's well-known (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Descriptions.Stephen Neale - 1990 - MIT Press.
    When philosophers talk about descriptions, usually they have in mind singular definite descriptions such as ‘the finest Greek poet’ or ‘the positive square root of nine’, phrases formed with the definite article ‘the’. English also contains indefinite descriptions such as ‘a fine Greek poet’ or ‘a square root of nine’, phrases formed with the indefinite article ‘a’ (or ‘an’); and demonstrative descriptions (also known as complex demonstratives) such as ‘this Greek poet’ and ‘that tall woman’, formed with the demonstrative articles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.McCulloch Gregory, Evans Gareth & McDowell John - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (137):515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Structured propositions and complex predicates.Jeffrey C. King - 1995 - Noûs 29 (4):516-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Frege's Puzzle. [REVIEW]Graeme Forbes - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (3):455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   299 citations  
  • Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong.Jerry A. Fodor - 1998 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    The renowned philosopher Jerry Fodor, a leading figure in the study of the mind for more than twenty years, presents a strikingly original theory on the basic constituents of thought. He suggests that the heart of cognitive science is its theory of concepts, and that cognitive scientists have gone badly wrong in many areas because their assumptions about concepts have been mistaken. Fodor argues compellingly for an atomistic theory of concepts, deals out witty and pugnacious demolitions of rival theories, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   616 citations  
  • Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and Epistemology of Demonstratives and other Indexicals.David Kaplan - 1989 - In Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes From Kaplan. Oxford University Press. pp. 481-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1704 citations  
  • Presumptive meanings: the theory of generalized conversational implicature.Stephen C. Levinson - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    When we speak, we mean more than we say. In this book Stephen C. Levinson explains some general processes that underlie presumptions in communication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   429 citations  
  • On sense and reflexivity.John Justice - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (7):351-364.
    "On Sense and Reflexivity" offers the answer to a crucial question that was posed, and left without a satisfactory answer, by Gottlob Frege in "On Sense and Reference" (1892): What is the sense of a proper name? The century-long failure to answer this question has been the main motivation and support for recent nondescriptional accounts of lexical singular terms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • [Omnibus Review]. [REVIEW]David Kaplan - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):246-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Has the description theory of names been refuted.Jerrold J. Katz - 1990 - In George S. Boolos (ed.), Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press. pp. 31--61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong, by Jerry A. Fodor. [REVIEW]R. De Clercq - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 62 (3):609-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Frege's Puzzle. [REVIEW]Jan Wolenski - 1988 - Studia Logica 47 (4):439-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • The Individuation of Proper Names.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1980 - In Z. Van Straaten (ed.), Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P.F. Strawson. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 140--163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Descriptions.S. Neale - 1996 - Critica 28 (83):97-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   313 citations  
  • Semantics/pragmatics distinction.Robyn Carston & Gower Street - unknown
    Most people working on linguistic meaning or communication assume that semantics and pragmatics are distinct domains, yet there is still little consensus on how the distinction is to be drawn. The position defended in this paper is that the semantics/pragmatics distinction holds between (context-invariant) encoded linguistic meaning and speaker meaning. Two other ‘minimalist’ positions on semantics are explored and found wanting: Kent Bach’s view that there is a narrow semantic notion of context which is responsible for providing semantic values for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations