Switch to: Citations

References in:

Albert of saxony

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Free fall from Albert of Saxony to Honoré Fabri.Stillman Drake - 1975 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 5 (4):347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Albert of Saxony.John Longeway - 1995 - In Robert Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. New York City: Cambridge University Press. pp. 15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unconfusing Merely Confused Supposition in Albert of Saxony.Michael J. Fitzgerald - 2012 - Vivarium 50 (2):161-189.
    In this essay I argue that Albert would reject the need for a separate fourth mode of common personal supposition, and that his view of merely confused supposition has not been fully explicated by modern scholars. I first examine the various examples of conjunct descent given by modern scholars from his Perutilis logica , and show that Albert clearly adopts it in resolving the sophistic examples involved. Second, I explicate the view of merely confused supposition that Albert defends in his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Buridan School Reassessed. John Buridan and Albert of Saxony. Thijssen - 2004 - Vivarium 42 (1):18-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Impact of Ockham's Reading of the Physics On the Mertonians and Parisian Terminists.André Goddu - 2001 - Early Science and Medicine 6 (3):204-236.
    This article summarizes Ockham's interpretation of Aristotle's categories, showing how his account of connotative concepts introduced a revision in the Aristotelian doctrine about the relation between mathematics and physics. The article shows that Ockham's account influenced William of Heytesbury, John Dumbleton, and Nicholas Oresme to re-interpret disciplinary relations and disciplinary boundaries. They did so, however, in ways compatible with other basic principles of Aristotelian philosophy of nature; nevertheless, their modifications of the Aristotelian account of mathematics stimulated later philosophers to construct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Time as a Part of Physical Objects: The Modern 'Descartes-Minus Argument' and an Analogous Argument from Fourteenth-Century Logic (William Heytesbury and Albert of Saxony).Michael Fitzgerald - 2009 - Vivarium 47 (1):54-73.
    I argue in the essay that the fourteenth-century logicians William Heytesbury and Albert of Saxony developed an argument I call the Socrates-Minus Argument. Their analysis and rejection of it indicates a direction towards a pragmatic resolution to the contemporary Descartes-Minus Argument. Their resolution is similar to the view adopted today by Peter van Inwagen, namely, that “arbitrary undetached parts of physical objects,” like 'all of Socrates except his finger' simply do not exist. I conclude the fourteenth-century approach does not run (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Les sophismes du savoir: Albert de Saxe entre Jean Buridan et Guillaume Heytesbury.Joël Biard - 1989 - Vivarium 27 (1):36-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Scientific imagination in the middle ages.Edward Grant - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (4):394-423.
    : Following Aristotle, medieval natural philosophers believed that knowledge was ultimately based on perception and observation; and like Aristotle, they also believed that observation could not explain the "why" of any perception. To arrive at the "why," natural philosophers offered theoretical explanations that required the use of the imagination. This was, however, only the starting point. Not only did they apply their imaginations to real phenomena, but expended even more intellectual energy on counterfactual phenomena, both extracosmic and intracosmic, extensively discussing, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ein Albert von Sachsen zugeschriebener Physikkommentar aus der Mitte des 14. Jahrhunderts.Jurgen Sarnowsky - 2002 - Medioevo 27:449-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Logico-Mathematical Antinomies.Anton Dumitriu - 1974 - International Philosophical Quarterly 14 (3):309-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Die aristotelisch-scholastische Theorie der Bewegung. Studien zum Kommentar Alberts von Sachsen zur Physik des Aristoteles.Jürgen Sarnowsky - 1991 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 53 (2):356-357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • De la logique a la physique: Quantité et mouvement selon Albert de Saxe.Joël Biard - 1996 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 3:361-374.
    Tout au long de la période médiévale, la logique est un instrument privilégié d'acquisition et d'exposition des autres savoirs. Dans cet article, on se propose d'évaluer la portée de son investissement dans le champ de la philosophie naturelle, à partir d'un exemple: celui d'Albert de Saxe . A travers l'étude de la quantité et du mouvement, on voit se mettre en place une approche originale du corps naturel. All along the Medieval period, logic is an instrument for acquisition and exposition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lessons on truth from mediaeval solutions to the liar paradox.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2011 - Philosophical Quarterly 61 (242):58-78.
    Some fourteenth-century treatises on paradoxes of the liar family offer a promising starting-point for the formulation of full-fledged theories of truth with systematic relevance in their own right. In particular, Bradwardine's thesis that sentences typically say more than one thing gives rise to a quantificational approach to truth, and Buridan's theory of truth based on the notion of suppositio allows for remarkable metaphysical parsimony. Bradwardine's and Buridan's theories both have theoretical advantages, but fail to provide a satisfactory account of truth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Schlussfolgerungslehre in Erfurter Schulen des 14. Jahrhunderts: eine Untersuchung der Konsequentientraktate von Thomas Maulfelt und Albert von Sachsen in Gegenüberstellung mit einer zeitgenössischen Position.Rainer Grass - 2003 - John Benjamins Publishing.
    As the title indicates the author presents a contemporary theory of consequence. In so doing he establishes a terminology that enables a description, interpretation and evaluation of medieval theory independently of medieval vocabulary. In the interest of better understanding the medieval writers the author puts himself in the position of the medieval scholar in Erfurt. The reader learns about the Erfurt schools and the controversal debate on the so-called modi significandi, using only texts that are known to have been available (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Role of ‘Denotatur’ in Ockham’s Theory of Supposition.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2013 - Vivarium 51 (1-4):352-370.
    In the scholarship on medieval logic and semantics of the last decades, Ockham’s theory of supposition is probably the most extensively studied version of such theories; yet, it seems that we still do not fully understand all its intricacies. In this paper, I focus on a phrase that occurs countless times throughout Ockham’s writings, but in particular in the sections dedicated to supposition in the Summa logicae: the phrase ‘denotatur’. I claim that an adequate understanding of the role of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Die Eigenschaften der Termini: Eine Untersuchung Zur perutilis Logica Alberts von Sachsen.Christoph Kann - 1994 - New York: Brill. Edited by Albertus.
    The 'Perutilis logica' is both by its content and its didactic value the most paradigmatic logical compendium of the 14th century. The study presented here tries to show on the basis of an interpretative analysis of the second treatise that the doctrine of the properties of terms is stated in a unusually developed form in the 'Perutilis logica' and that suggestions that it lacks originality must be revised.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • When the Inference 'p is true, therefore p' Fails: John Buridan on the Evaluation of Propositions.Ernesto Perini-Santos - 2013 - Vivarium 51 (1-4):411-424.
    For John Buridan, truth-bearers are assertions. This fact explains why the inference ‘p is true, therefore p’ may fail. On the one hand, the tense of the verb plus the time of utterance do not determine the time about which a sentence is intended to be true: the intention of the speaker is needed. On the other hand, since the meaning of vocal and written words is conventional, it may seem that they can be used with different meanings on each (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Parisian psychology in the mid-fourteenth century.P. Marshall - 1983 - Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Âge 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Albert von Sachsen . 3. Fortsetzung und Ergänzungen zur Bibliographie der Sekundärliteratur.H. Berger - 1998 - Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale 40:103-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Überlegungen zur Identitätstheorie der Prädikation.Richard Gaskin - 1997 - Wissenschaft Und Weisheit 60 (1):87-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Problems with temporality and scientific propositions in John Buridan and Albert of saxony.Michael Fitzgerald - 2006 - Vivarium 44 (s 2-3):305-337.
    The essay develops two major arguments. First, if John Buridan's 'first argument' for the reintroduction of natural supposition is only that the "eternal truth" of a scientific proposition is preserved because subject terms in scientific propositions supposit for all the term's past, present, and future significata indifferently; then Albert of Saxony thinks it is simply ineffective. Only the 'second argument', i.e. the argument for the existence of an 'atemporal copula', adequately performs this task; but is rejected by Albert. Second, later (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Modal Logic of Albert of Saxony.Pamela Ely - 1981 - Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada)
    This work is an exegetical account of the modal logic of Albert of Saxony, a 14th century logician and scientist. The text used was the 1522 Venice edition of the Perutilis logica. As there is no critical edition of the text, a "working edition" of the pertinent sections accompanies the dissertation as an appendix. ;Aristotle's modal logic which served as a basis for modal logic in the Middle Ages is briefly reviewed. Albert's non-modal propositional logic, onto which the modal logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation