Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Recognition : Fichte and Hegel on the Other.[author unknown] - 1992 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 56 (2):371-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Hegel: A Biography.Paul Redding - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):470-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Inseparability of Love and Anguish.Robert R. Williams - 2012 - In Angelica Nuzzo (ed.), Hegel on Religion and Politics. State University of New York Press. pp. 133-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Introduction.Jere O’Neill Surber - 2006 - In Jere O'Neill Surber (ed.), Hegel and Language. State University of New York Press. pp. 1-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Objective Language and Scientific Truth in Hegel.Jeffrey Reid - 2006 - In Jere O'Neill Surber (ed.), Hegel and Language. State University of New York Press. pp. 95-110.
    The paper explores Hegel's theory of language, from the Subjective Spirit book of his Encyclopedia. Hegel distinguishes between linguistic signs, as arbitrary signifiers and words, which occur when the signs are filled with thought or meaning. Words have greater objectivity than signs. The words of the positive, empirical sciences are taken up into Hegelian Science (system), affording it greater objectivity, which it, reciprocally re-confers on its linguistic contents.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some Metaphysical Implications of Hegel’s Theodicy.Paul Redding - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (1):129--150.
    This paper examines Hegel’s claim that philosophy “has no other object than God‘ as a claim about the essentiality of the idea of God to philosophy. On this idealist interpretation, even atheistic philosophies would presuppose rationally evaluable ideas of God, despite denials of the existence of anything corresponding to those ideas. This interpretation is then applied to Hegel’s version of idealism in relation to those of two predecessors, Leibniz and Kant. Hegel criticizes the idea of the Christian God present within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hegel on Logic and Religion: The Reasonableness of Christianity.Terry Pinkard & John W. Burbidge - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (2):375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Metaphysics without Pre-Critical Monism: Hegel on Lower-Level Natural Kinds and the Structure of Reality.James Kreines - 2008 - Hegel Bulletin 29 (1-2):48-70.
    Recent debates about Hegel's theoretical philosophy are marked by a surprising lack of agreement, extending all the way down to the most basic question:what is Hegel talking about?On the one hand, proponents of ‘metaphysical’ interpretations generally read Hegel as aiming to articulate the overall structure or organisation of reality itself, and the nature of a highest or most fundamental being. Particularly influential is the idea that Hegel is reviving and modifying a form of Spinoza's metaphysical monism, according to which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Hegel's metaphysics: Changing the debate.James Kreines - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (5):466–480.
    There are two general approaches to Hegel’s theoretical philosophy which are broadly popular in recent work. Debate between them is often characterized, by both sides, as a dispute between those favoring a more traditional “metaphysical” approach and those favoring a newer “nonmetaphysical” approach. But I argue that the most important and compelling points made by both sides are actually independent of the idea of a “nonmetaphysical” interpretation of Hegel, which is itself simply unconvincing. The most promising directions for future research, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Between the Bounds of experience and divine intuition: Kant's epistemic limits and Hegel's ambitions.James Kreines - 2007 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):306 – 334.
    Hegel seeks to overturn Kant's conclusion that our knowledge is restricted, or that we cannot have knowledge of things as they are in themselves. Understanding this Hegelian ambition requires distinguishing two Kantian characterizations of our epistemic limits: First, we can have knowledge only within the "bounds of experience". Second, we cannot have knowledge of objects that would be accessible only to a divine intellectual intuition, even though the faculty of reason requires us to conceive of such objects. Hegel aims to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Outside ethics.Raymond Geuss - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (1):29–53.
    Outside Ethics brings together some of the most important and provocative works by one of the most creative philosophers writing today. Seeking to expand the scope of contemporary moral and political philosophy, Raymond Geuss here presents essays bound by a shared skepticism about a particular way of thinking about what is important in human life--a way of thinking that, in his view, is characteristic of contemporary Western societies and isolates three broad categories of things as important: subjective individual preferences, knowledge, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature.Erich Auerbach & Willard R. Trask - 1954 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 12 (4):526-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The Relevance of Hegel’s “Absolute Spirit” to Social Normativity.Paul Redding - 2011 - In Heikki Ikaheimo & Arto Laitinen (eds.), Recognition and Social Ontology. Leiden: Brill. pp. 212--238.
    Around the turn of the twentieth century, Wilhelm Dilthey, in his reflections on the nature of history as a “Geisteswissenschaft”—a science of “spirit” as opposed to “nature”—appealed “to Hegel’s notion of “spirit” (Geist). Attempting to extract Hegel’s concept from what he considered the unsupportable metaphysical system within which it had been developed, Dilthey, a neo-Kantian, gave it a broadly epistemological significance by correlating it with a distinct type of “understanding” (Verstehen) that was foreign to the Naturwissenschaften, concerned as they were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hegel, Recognition, and Religion.Damion Buterin - 2011 - Review of Metaphysics 64 (4):789-821.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hegel, Idealism and God: Philosophy as the Self-Correcting Appropriation of the Norms of Life and Thought.Paul Redding - 2007 - Cosmos and History : The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy 3 (2-3):16-31.
    Can Hegel, a philosopher who claims that philosophy lsquo;has no other object but God and so is essentially rational theologyrsquo;, ever be taken as anything emother than/em a religious philosopher with little to say to any philosophical project that identifies itself as emsecular/em?nbsp; If the valuable substantive insights found in the detail of Hegelrsquo;s philosophy are to be rescued for a secular philosophy, then, it is commonly presupposed, some type of global reinterpretation of the enframing idealistic framework is required. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hegel’s Concept of God,.Quentin Lauer - 1982, - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (1):136-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations