Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. How Can I Be Trusted?: A Virtue Theory of Trustworthiness.Nancy Nyquist Potter - 2002 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    This work examines the concept of trust in the light of virtue theory, and takes our responsibility to be trustworthy as central. Rather than thinking of trust as risk-taking, Potter views it as equally a matter of responsibility-taking. Her work illustrates that relations of trust are never independent from considerations of power, and that asking ourselves what we can do to be trustworthy allows us to move beyond adversarial trust relationships and toward a more democratic, just, and peaceful society.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Understanding Trust.Carolyn McLeod - 2004 - In Françoise Baylis, Jocelyn Downie, Barry Hoffmaster & Susan Sherwin (eds.), Health Care Ethics in Canada. Harcourt Brace. pp. 186--92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Trust and antitrust.Annette Baier - 1986 - Ethics 96 (2):231-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   602 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Critical Moral Ethnography of Social Distrust.Jessica Prata Miller - 2000 - Social Philosophy Today 16:141-158.
    This paper explores the ways in which trust and distrust, especially among relative strangers, are connected to social identities and locations. It begins by sketching an account of interpersonal trust, emphasizing the role that socially salient identities, based in part upon cultural figurations, play in their development. It then contends that these cultural figurations both foster and result from distrust of specific social groups, including African Americans, the poor, and (some) women. Treating social roles and relations as central to moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Individuals-in-communities: The search for a feminist model of epistemic subjects.Heidi E. Grasswick - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (3):85-120.
    : Feminist epistemologists have found the atomistic view of knowers provided by classical epistemology woefully inadequate. An obvious alternative for feminists is Lynn Hankinson Nelson's suggestion that it is communities that know. However, I argue that Nelson's view is problematic for feminists, and I offer instead a conception of knowers as "individuals-in-communities." This conception is preferable, given the premises and goals of feminist epistemologists, because it emphasizes the relations between knowers and their communities and the relevance of these relations for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Critical Moral Ethnography of Social Distrust.Jessica Prata Miller - 2000 - Social Philosophy Today 16:141-158.
    This paper explores the ways in which trust and distrust, especially among relative strangers, are connected to social identities and locations. It begins by sketching an account of interpersonal trust, emphasizing the role that socially salient identities, based in part upon cultural figurations, play in their development. It then contends that these cultural figurations both foster and result from distrust of specific social groups, including African Americans, the poor, and (some) women. Treating social roles and relations as central to moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Opioid Contracts and Random Drug Testing for People with Chronic Pain — Think Twice.Mark Collen - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (4):841-845.
    The use of opioid contracts, which often require patients to submit to random drug screens, have become widespread amongst physicians using opioids to treat chronic pain. The main purpose of the contract is to improve care through better adherence to opioid therapy but there is little evidence as to its efficacy. The author suggests the use of opioid contracts and random drug testing destroys patients' trust which impacts health outcomes, and that physicians' motivation for their use are concerns about prosecution, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Opioid Contracts and Random Drug Testing for People with Chronic Pain — Think Twice.Mark Collen - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (4):841-845.
    It is common for physicians who prescribe opioids for chronic pain to have their patients sign an opioid contract in order to receive opioid therapy. A vast majority of these contracts contain a stipulation requiring patients to submit to random drug testing which screens for both licit and illicit drugs. Physicians who prescribe opioids may be concerned about prosecution and disciplinary actions; medication abuse and misuse; and addiction. Steven Passik et al. write, “…physicians still fear the risk of abuse or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Medical Education for Pain and Addiction: Making Progress Toward Answering a Need.Sidney H. Schnoll & James Finch - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (3):252-256.
    Pain is one of the most frequent presenting symptoms for patients who come to a physician's office. Despite the frequency of this presentation, little consistent, systematic information is provided to medical students or physicians about the treatment of pain. In addition, relatively little information is given about the recognition and prevention of drug abuse and about how to prescribe analgesics rationally to minimize the chances for abuse. This lack of educational preparation for both pain and addiction contributes to significant fear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Medical Education for Pain and Addiction: Making Progress Toward Answering a Need.Sidney H. Schnoll & James Finch - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (3):252-256.
    Pain is one of the most frequent presenting symptoms for patients who come to a physician's office. Despite the frequency of this presentation, little consistent, systematic information is provided to medical students or physicians about the treatment of pain. In addition, relatively little information is given about the recognition and prevention of drug abuse and about how to prescribe analgesics rationally to minimize the chances for abuse. This lack of educational preparation for both pain and addiction contributes to significant fear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The other side of trust in health care: Prescribing drugs with the potential for abuse.Jessica Miller - 2006 - Bioethics 21 (1):51–60.
    ABSTRACT Defining a nonpaternalistic yet achievable form of trust in medicine in an era of simultaneous patient empowerment and institutional control has been and remains an important task of bioethics. The ‘crisis of trust’ in medicine has been viewed mainly as the problem of getting patients to trust their health care providers, especially physicians. However, since paradigmatic cases of trust are mutual, bioethicists must pay more attention to physician trust in patients. A physician’s view of the reasonableness of trust in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Trust: The scarcest of medical resources.Patricia Illingworth - 2002 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 27 (1):31 – 46.
    In this paper, I claim that the doctor-patient relationship can be viewed as a vessel of trust. Nonetheless, trust within the doctor-patient relationship has been impaired by managed care. When we conceive of trust as social capital, focusing on the role that it plays in individual and social well-being, trust can be viewed as a public good and a scarce medical resource. Given this, there is a moral obligation to protect the doctor-patient relationship from the cost-containment mechanisms that compromise its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Trusting experts and epistemic humility in disability.Anita Ho - 2011 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 4 (2):102-123.
    It is generally accepted that the therapeutic relationship between professionals and patients is one of trust. Nonetheless, some patient groups carry certain social vulnerabilities that can be exacerbated when they extend trust to health-care professionals. In exploring the epistemic and ethical implications of expert status, this paper examines how calls to trust may increase epistemic oppression and perpetuate the vulnerability of people with impairments. It critically evaluates the processes through which epistemic communities are formed or determined, and examines the institutional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Gender and trust in medicine: Vulnerabilities, abuses, and remedies.Wendy Rogers & Angela Ballantyne - 2008 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 1 (1):48-66.
    Trust is taken to be one of the foundational values in the doctor-patient relationship, facilitating access to the benefits of health care and providing a guarantee against possible harms. Despite this foundational role, some doctors betray the trust of their patients. Trusting involves granting discretionary powers and makes the truster vulnerable to the trustee. Patients trust medical practitioners to act with goodwill and to act competently. Some patients carry pre-existing vulnerabilities, for reasons such as gender, poverty, age, ethnicity, or disability, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On the Erroneous Conflation of Opiophobia and the Undertreatment of Pain.Daniel S. Goldberg - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (11):20-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations