Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Special Divine Action and How to Do Philosophy of Religion.Patrick Giddy - 2011 - South African Journal of Philosophy 30 (2):143-154.
    Any notion of a god that is of relevance to us must show how it makes a difference in the world. But this idea of an interventionist god doesn’t make sense for a secular and scientific mentality such as ours. I take Brenda de Wet’s five sticking points for any religious believer that seem to fail to make the grade of intellectual integrity (2008), and argue that starting from creedal and popular formulations of the notion of a god, as she (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Divine intervention and the conservation of energy: a reply to Evan Fales. [REVIEW]Robert Larmer - 2014 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 75 (1):27-38.
    Evan Fales has recently argued that, although I provide the most promising approach for those concerned to defend belief in divine intervention, I nevertheless fail to show that such belief can be rational. I argue that Fales’ objections are unsuccessful.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Falsifiability and traction in theories of divine action.Kile Jones - 2010 - Zygon 45 (3):575-589.
    One of the most focused research programs in the science-religion dialogue that has taken place up to the present is the series of volumes published jointly by the Vatican Observatory and the Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences. Originating with the encouragement of Pope John Paul II, this series has produced seven volumes focusing on how divine action can be understood in light of contemporary science. A retrospective volume published in 2008, Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action: Twenty Years of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Divine action in the world (synopsis).Alvin Plantinga - 2006 - Ratio 19 (4):495–504.
    The following is a synopsis of the paper presented by Alvin Plantinga at the RATIO conference on The Meaning of Theism held in April 2005 at the University of Reading. The synopsis has been prepared by the Editor, with the author’s approval, from a handout provided by the author at the conference. The paper reflects on whether religious belief of a traditional Christian kind can be maintained consistently with accepting our modern scientific worldview. Many theologians, and also many scientists, maintain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can Western Monotheism Avoid Substance Dualism?Dennis Bielfeldt - 2001 - Zygon 36 (1):153-177.
    The problem of divine agency and action is analogous to the problem of human agency and action: How is such agency possible in the absence of a dualistic causal interaction between disparate orders of being? This paper explores nondualistic accounts of divine agency that assert the following: (1) physical monism, (2) antireductionism, (3) physical realization, and (4) divine causal realism. I conclude that a robustly causal deity is incompatible with nonddualism's affirmation of physical monism. Specifically, I argue the incoherence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • O pewnej próbie obrony wyjaśniania teleologicznego.Zbigniew Wróblewski - 2012 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 60 (4):339-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)A world of contingencies.Robert E. Ulanowicz - 2013 - Zygon 48 (1):77-92.
    Physicalism holds that the laws of physics are inviolable and ubiquitous and thereby account for all of reality. Laws leave no “wiggle room” or “gaps” for action by numinous agents. They cannot be invoked, however, without boundary stipulations that perforce are contingent and which “drive” the laws. Driving contingencies are not limited to instances of “blind chance,” but rather span a continuum of amalgamations with regularities, up to and including nearly determinate propensities. Most examples manifest directionality, and their very definition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Creation and End-Directedness.John F. Owens - 2010 - Sophia 49 (4):489-498.
    Does the act of creation show itself anywhere within the creation? A common contemporary ontology tends to see two possibilities for those who want to defend a notion of creation. The first is to argue that an original set of materials was brought into existence out of nothing by divine action a long time ago. The second, in the tradition of Paley, posits a specific divine action that oversees the development of some of the materials into entities with an end-directedness. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Particular divine action: a challenge to intellectual integrity in a post-Christian age.Brenda de Wet - 2008 - South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (2):91-103.
    The fact that certain configurations of problems and the philosophical antinomies, paradoxes and confusions they contain regularly return in the history of the rational exposition of these problems points to more than the limitations of human reason and the inexhaustibility of the subject matter; it is indicative of a structural problem . If we agree that integrity is defined as the quality of being unimpaired based on unity or wholeness, then holding beliefs based on theories compromised by structural problems jeopardises (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evaluating the teleological argument for divine action.Wesley J. Wildman - 2009 - In Fount LeRon Shults, Nancey C. Murphy & Robert John Russell (eds.), Philosophy, science and divine action. Boston: Brill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolution and subjectivity.William P. Kiblinger - 2007 - Zygon 42 (1):193-202.
    Evolutionary theory is becoming an all-encompassing form of explanation in many branches of philosophy. However, emergence theory uses the concept of self-organization to support yet alter traditional evolutionary explanation. Biologist Stuart Kauffman suggests that the new science will need to tell stories, not simply as a heuristic device but as part of its fundamental task. This claim is reminiscent of C. S. Peirce’s criticism of the doctrine of necessity. Peirce’s suggestions reference Hegel, and this essay draws out this Hegelian background. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Niebezpieczny naturalizm Freemana Dysona.Michał Heller - 2003 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 51 (3):119-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Twarde jądro ewolucjonizmu.Kazimierz Jodkowski - 2003 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 51 (3):77-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)A world of contingencies.Robert E. Ulanowicz - 2013 - Zygon 48 (1):77-92.
    Physicalism holds that the laws of physics are inviolable and ubiquitous and thereby account for all of reality. Laws leave no “wiggle room” or “gaps” for action by numinous agents. They cannot be invoked, however, without boundary stipulations that perforce are contingent and which “drive” the laws. Driving contingencies are not limited to instances of “blind chance,” but rather span a continuum of amalgamations with regularities, up to and including nearly determinate propensities. Most examples manifest directionality, and their very definition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations