Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Animal Liberation.Bill Puka & Peter Singer - 1977 - Philosophical Review 86 (4):557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   622 citations  
  • Epistemology and Environmental Values.Bryan G. Norton - 1992 - The Monist 75 (2):208-226.
    Gifford Pinchot, the first official U.S. Forester, wrote: “There are just two things on this material earth—people and natural resources.” This philosophy apparently implies that all things other than people have only instrumental value. Environmentalists, even professional foresters, today believe that Gifford Pinchot’s system of forest management is both theoretically and practically inadequate. A difficult, and central, problem in the theory of environmental management is therefore to characterize exactly how Pinchot went wrong. If we knew that, we would be well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The Varieties of Intrinsic Value.John O’Neill - 1992 - The Monist 75 (2):119-137.
    To hold an environmental ethic is to hold that non-human beings and states of affairs in the natural world have intrinsic value. This seemingly straightforward claim has been the focus of much recent philosophical discussion of environmental issues. Its clarity is, however, illusory. The term ‘intrinsic value’ has a variety of senses and many arguments on environmental ethics suffer from a conflation of these different senses: specimen hunters for the fallacy of equivocation will find rich pickings in the area. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • (1 other version)Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness Perservation: A Third World Critique.Ramachandra Guha - 1989 - Environmental Ethics 11 (1):71-83.
    I present a Third World critique of the trend in American environmentalism known as deep ecology, analyzing each of deep ecology’s central tenets: the distinction between anthropocentrism and biocentrism, the focus on wildemess preservation, the invocation of Eastem traditions, and the belief that it represents the most radical trend within environmentalism. I argue that the anthropocentrism/biocentrism distinction is of little use in understanding the dynamics of environmental degredation, that the implementation of the wildemess agenda is causing serious deprivation in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • (1 other version)Radical American environmentalism and wilderness preservation : a Third World critique.Ramachandra Guha - 2010 - In Craig Hanks (ed.), Technology and values: essential readings. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 71-83.
    I present a Third World critique of the trend in American environmentalism known as deep ecology, analyzing each of deep ecology’s central tenets: the distinction between anthropocentrism and biocentrism, the focus on wildemess preservation, the invocation of Eastem traditions, and the belief that it represents the most radical trend within environmentalism. I argue that the anthropocentrism/biocentrism distinction is of little use in understanding the dynamics of environmental degredation, that the implementation of the wildemess agenda is causing serious deprivation in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Are Species Really Individuals?David L. Hull - 1976 - Systematic Zoology 25:174–191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  • A Radical Solution to the Species Problem.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1974 - Systematic Zoology 23 (4):536–544.
    Traditionally, species have been treated as classes. In fact they may be considered individuals. The logical term “individual” has been confused with a biological synonym for “organism.” If species are individuals, then: 1) their names are proper, 2) there cannot be instances of them, 3) they do not have defining properties, 4) their constituent organisms are parts, not members. “ Species " may be defined as the most extensive units in the natural economy such that reproductive competition occurs among their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   295 citations  
  • An examination and defense of one argument concerning animal rights.Tom Regan - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):189 – 219.
    An argument is examined and defended for extending basic moral rights to animals which assumes that humans, including infants and the severely mentally enfeebled, have such rights. It is claimed that this argument proceeds on two fronts, one critical, where proposed criteria of right-possession are rejected, the other constructive, where proposed criteria are examined with a view to determining the most reasonable one. This form of argument is defended against the charge that it is self-defeating, various candidates for the title, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The shallow and the deep, long-range ecology movement. A summary.Arne Naess - 1973 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-4):95 – 100.
    Ecologically responsible policies are concerned only in part with pollution and resource depletion. There are deeper concerns which touch upon principles of diversity, complexity, autonomy, decentralization, symbiosis, egalitarianism, and classlessness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   271 citations  
  • Before environmental ethics.Anthony Weston - 1992 - Environmental Ethics 14 (4):321-338.
    Contemporary nonanthropocentic environmental ethics is profoundly shaped by the very anthropocentrism that it tries to transcend. New values only slowly struggle free of old contexts. Recognizing this struggle, however, opens a space for—indeed, necessitates—alternative models for contemporary environmental ethics. Rather than trying to unify or fine-tune our theories, we require more pluralistic andexploratory methods. We cannot reach theoretical finality; we can only co-evolve an ethic with transformed practices.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Beyond intrinsic value: Pragmatism in environmental ethics.Anthony Weston - 1985 - Environmental Ethics 7 (4):321-339.
    In this essay I propose an environmental ethic in the pragmatic vein. I begin by suggesting that the contemporary debate in environmental ethics is forced into a familiar but highly restrictive set of distinctions and problems by the traditional notion of intrinsic value, particularly by its demands that intrinsic values be self-sufficient, abstract, and justified in special ways. I criticize this notion and develop an alternativewhich stresses the interdependent structure of values, a structure which at once roots them deeply in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Environmental ethics and weak anthropocentrism.Bryan G. Norton - 1984 - Environmental Ethics 6 (2):131-148.
    The assumption that environmental ethics must be nonanthropocentric in order to be adequate is mistaken. There are two forms of anthropocentrism, weak and strong, and weak anthropocentrism is adequate to support an environmental ethic. Environmental ethics is, however, distinctive vis-a-vis standard British and American ethical systems because, in order to be adequate, it must be nonindividualistic.Environmental ethics involves decisions on two levels, one kind of which differs from usual decisions affecting individual fairness while the other does not. The latter, called (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Valuing wildlands.Iii Holmes Rolston - 1985 - Environmental Ethics 7 (1):23-48.
    Valuing wildlands is complex. (1) In a philosophically oriented analysis, I distinguish seven meaning levels of value, individual preference, market price, individual good, social preference, social good, organismic, and ecosystemic, and itemize twelve types of value carried by wildlands, economic, life support, recreational, scientific, genetic diversity, aesthetic, cultural syrubolization, historical, characterbuilding, therapeutic, religious, and intrinsic. (2) I criticize contingent valuation efforts to price these values. (3) I then propose an axiological model, which interrelates the multiple levels and types of value, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On being morally considerable.Kenneth E. Goodpaster - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (6):308-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • (1 other version)Toward Unity among Environmentalists.Mark Sagoff & Bryan G. Norton - 1993 - Hastings Center Report 23 (2):42.
    Book reviewed in this article: Toward Unity among Environmentalists. By Bryan G. Norton.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • V. 1980.'Human chauvinism and environmental ethics'.R. Routley - 1980 - In Don S. Mannison, Michael A. McRobbie & Richard Sylvan (eds.), Environmental Philosophy. Dept. Of Philosophy, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic.Tom Regan - 1981 - Environmental Ethics 3 (1):19-34.
    A conception of an environmental ethic is set forth which involves postulating that nonconscious natural objects can have value in their own right, independently of human interests. Two kinds of objection are considered: those that deny the possibility of developing an ethic ofthe environment that accepts this postulate, and those.that deny the necessity of constructing such an ethic. Both types of objection are found wanting. The essay condudes with some tentative remarks regarding the notion of inherent value.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Values in Nature.Iii Holmes Rolston - 1981 - Environmental Ethics 3 (2):113-128.
    Nature is examined as a carrier of values. Despite problems of subjectivity and objectivity in value assignments, values are actualized in human relationships with nature, sometimes by constructive activity depending on a natural support, sometimes by a sensitive, if an interpretive, appreciation of the characteristics of natural objects. Ten areas of values associated with nature are recognized: economic value, life support value, recreational value, scientific value, aesthetic value, life value, diversity and unity values, stability and spontaneity values, dialectical value, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Why I am Not a Nonanthropocentrist: Callicott and the Failure of Monistic Inherentism.Bryan G. Norton - 1995 - Environmental Ethics 17 (4):341-358.
    I contrast two roles for environmental philosophers—“applied philosophy” and “practical philosophy”—and show that the strategy of applied philosophy encourages an axiological and monistic approach to theory building. I argue that the mission of applied philosophy, and the monistic theory defended by J. Baird Callicott, in particular, tends to separate philosophers and their problems from real management issues because applied philosophers and moral monists insist that theoretical exploration occurs independent of, and prior to, applications in particular situations. This separation of theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Epistemology and Intrinsic Values.Christopher J. Preston - 1998 - Environmental Ethics 20 (4):409-428.
    Debates over the existence of intrinsic value have long been central to professional environmental ethics. Holmes Rolston, III’s version of intrinsic value is, perhaps, the most well known. Recently, powerful critiques leveled by Bryan G. Norton and J. Baird Callicott have suggested that there is an epistemological problem with Rolston’s account. In this paper, I argue first that the debates over intrinsic value are as pertinent now as they have ever been. I then explain the objections that Norton and Callicott (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Background of Ecology: Concept and Theory.Robert P. Mcintosh - 1986 - Journal of the History of Biology 19 (2):314-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Is There an Ecological Ethic?Holmes Rolston - 1975 - Ethics 85 (2):93-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (1 other version)More on earth first! And the monkey wrench gang.Dave Foreman - 1983 - Environmental Ethics 5 (1):95-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Environmental Pragmatism.Andrew Light & Eric Katz - 1996 - Ethics and the Environment 2 (2):199-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • (3 other versions)The Case for Animal Rights.Tom Regan & Mary Midgley - 1986 - The Personalist Forum 2 (1):67-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   613 citations  
  • Staying Alive: Women, Ecology and Development.Vandana Shiva - 1991 - Hypatia 6 (1):206-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Thinking through Confucius.David L. Hall & Roger T. Ames - 1987 - Philosophy East and West 41 (2):241-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • Current Normative Concepts in Conservation.J. Baird Callicott, Larry B. Crowder & Karen Mumford - 1999 - Conservation Biology 13 (1):22-35.
    A plethora of normative conservation concepts have recently emerged, most of which are ill-defined: biological diversity, biological integrity, ecological restoration, ecological services, ecological rehabilitation, ecological sustainability, sustainable development, ecosystem health, ecosystem management, adaptive management, and keystone species are salient among them. These normative concepts can be organized and interpreted by reference to two new schools of conservation philosophy, compositionalism and functionalism. The former comprehends nature primarily by means of evolutionary ecology and considers Homo sapiens separate from nature. The latter comprehends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)Principia Ethica.George Edward Moore - 1903 - International Journal of Ethics 14 (3):377-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   564 citations  
  • Beyond the Land Ethic: More Essays in Environmental Philosophy.J. Baird Callicott - 2001 - Environmental Values 10 (1):138-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Conserving Natural Value.Holmes Rolston - 1996 - Environmental Ethics 18:209-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Discourse on Method.René Descartes - 1900 - The Monist 10:472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • What Does the Recognition of Intrinsic Value Entail?Warwick Fox - 1993 - The Trumpeter 10 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations