Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Geometrical and physical conventionalism of Henri poincar'e in epistemological formulation.Jerzy Giedymin - 1991 - Studies in the History and Philsophy of Science 22 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Geometrical and physical conventionalism of Henri Poincaré in epistemological formulation.Jerzy Giedymin - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 22 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Les géométries non euclidiennes, le problème philosophique de l’espace et la conception transcendantale; Helmholtz et Kant, les néo-kantiens, Einstein, Poincaré et Mach.Luciano Boi - 1996 - Kant Studien 87 (3):257-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Poincaré's philosophy of space.Jules Vuillemin - 1972 - Synthese 24 (1-2):161 - 179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Rise of non-Archimedean Mathematics and the Roots of a Misconception I: The Emergence of non-Archimedean Systems of Magnitudes.Philip Ehrlich - 2006 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 60 (1):1-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • L'infinitesimo fra storia e filosofia della matematica.Dario Palladino - 1987 - Epistemologia 10 (1):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Foundations of Geometry and the Concept of Motion: Helmholtz and Poincaré.Gerhard Heinzmann - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (3):457-470.
    ArgumentAccording to Hermann von Helmholtz, free mobility of bodies seemed to be an essential condition of geometry. This free mobility can be interpreted either as matter of fact, as a convention, or as a precondition making measurements in geometry possible. Since Henri Poincaré defined conventions as principles guided by experience, the question arises in which sense experiential data can serve as the basis for the constitution of geometry. Helmholtz considered muscular activity to be the basis on which the form of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Helmholtz's naturalized conception of geometry and his spatial theory of signs.David Jalal Hyder - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):286.
    I analyze the two main theses of Helmholtz's "The Applicability of the Axioms to the Physical World," in which he argued that the axioms of Euclidean geometry are not, as his neo-Kantian opponents had argued, binding on any experience of the external world. This required two argumentative steps: 1) a new account of the structure of our representations which was consistent both with the experience of our (for him) Euclidean world and with experience of a non-Euclidean one, and 2) a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • La vérité en géométrie: sur le rejet mathématique de la doctrine conventionnaliste.Scott A. Walter - 1997 - Philosophia Scientiae 2 (3):103-135.
    The reception of Poincaré’s conventionalist doctrine of space by mathematicians is studied for the period 1891–1911. The opposing view of Riemann and Helmholtz, according to which the geometry of space is an empirical question, is shown to have swayed several geometers. This preference is considered in the context of changing views of the nature of space in theoretical physics, and with respect to structural and social changes within mathematics. Included in the latter evolution is the emergence of non-Euclidean geometry as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Bibliographie des travaux sur l’oeuvre de Poincaré (2001-2005).Philippe Nabonnand - 2005 - Philosophia Scientiae 9 (1):195-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Natural and the Normative. [REVIEW]Gordon G. Brittan Jr - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):432-434.
    I said that the book is brilliant. This is not so much because of the conclusions eventually reached about the inadequacy of a purely naturalistic approach to mind. These conclusions are already familiar in the work of Donald Davidson and others. Rather, it is because of the accumulation of historical detail and insight on the basis of which these conclusions are reached. It is often said, for instance, that Kant is a watershed figure, in some sense synthesizing and then moving (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations