Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Transgender Children and the Right to Transition: Medical Ethics When Parents Mean Well but Cause Harm.Maura Priest - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (2):45-59.
    Published in the American Journal of Bioethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Principles of Biomedical Ethics.Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (4):37.
    Book reviewed in this article: Principles of Biomedical Ethics. By Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2274 citations  
  • “I would have preferred more options”: accounting for non-binary youth in health research.Hélène Frohard-Dourlent, Sarah Dobson, Beth A. Clark, Marion Doull & Elizabeth M. Saewyc - 2017 - Nursing Inquiry 24 (1):e12150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Indeterminacy and the normative basis of the harm threshold for overriding parental decisions: a response to Birchley.Rosalind J. McDougall - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):119-120.
    Birchley9s critique of the harm threshold for overriding parental decisions is successful in demonstrating that the harm threshold, like the best interests standard, suffers from the problem of indeterminacy. However, his focus on critiquing empirical rather than normative arguments for the harm threshold means that his broad conclusion that it is ‘ill-judged’ is not justified. Advocates of the harm threshold can accept that the concept of harm to a child is indeterminate, yet still invoke strong normative arguments for this way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Best Interests Standard for Incompetent or Incapacitated Persons of All Ages.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2007 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (1):187-196.
    When making decisions for adults who lack decision-making capacity and have no discernable preferences, widespread support exists for using the Best Interests Standard. This policy appeals to adults and is compatible with many important recommendations for persons facing end-of-life choices.Common objections to the policy are discussed as well as different meanings of this Standard identified, such as using it to express goals or ideals and to make practical decisions incorporating what reasonable persons would want. For reasons of consistency, fairness, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Parental discretion and children's rights: Background and implications for medical decision-making.Ferdinand Schoeman - 1985 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10 (1):45-62.
    This paper argues that liberal tenats that justify intervention to promote the welfare of an incompetent do not suffice as a basis for analyzing parent-child relationships, and that this inadequacy is the basis for many of the problems that arise when thinking about the state's role in resolving family conflicts, particularly when monitoring parental discretion in medical decision-making on behalf of a child. The state may be limited by the best interest criterion when dealing with children, but parents are not. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Principles of biomedical ethics.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by James F. Childress.
    Over the course of its first seven editions, Principles of Biomedical Ethics has proved to be, globally, the most widely used, authored work in biomedical ethics. It is unique in being a book in bioethics used in numerous disciplines for purposes of instruction in bioethics. Its framework of moral principles is authoritative for many professional associations and biomedical institutions-for instruction in both clinical ethics and research ethics. It has been widely used in several disciplines for purposes of teaching in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1940 citations  
  • Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention.Douglas Diekema - 2004 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25 (4):243-264.
    Minors are generally considered incompetent to provide legally binding decisions regarding their health care, and parents or guardians are empowered to make those decisions on their behalf. Parental authority is not absolute, however, and when a parent acts contrary to the best interests of a child, the state may intervene. The best interests standard is the threshold most frequently employed in challenging a parent''s refusal to provide consent for a child''s medical care. In this paper, I will argue that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Common Morality, Coherence, and the Principles of Biomedical Ethics.David DeGrazia - 2003 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (3):219-230.
    : The fifth edition of Beauchamp and Childress's Principles of Biomedical Ethics is distinguished by its emphatic embrace of common morality as the ultimate source of moral norms. This essay critically evaluates the fifth edition's discussion of common morality and, to a lesser extent, its treatment of coherence (both the model of ethical justification and the associated concept). It is argued that the book is overly accommodating of existing moral beliefs. The paper concludes with three suggestions for improving this leading (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Contributions of Ethical Theory to Pediatric Ethics Pediatricians and Parents as Co-fiduciaries of Pediatric Patients.Laurence B. McCullough - forthcoming - Pediatric Bioethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pubertal Suppression and Professional Obligations: May a Pediatric Endocrinologist Refuse to Treat an Adolescent With Gender Dysphoria?Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (1):43-46.
    Of the different features of this case, I focus on the pediatric endocrinologist's refusal to treat the patient. Providers generally have wide latitude in accepting or refusing patients. Appropriat...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Overriding parents’ medical decisions for their children: a systematic review of normative literature.Rosalind J. McDougall & Lauren Notini - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (7):448-452.
    This paper reviews the ethical literature on conflicts between health professionals and parents about medical decision-making for children. We present the results of a systematic review which addressed the question ‘when health professionals and parents disagree about the appropriate course of medical treatment for a child, under what circumstances is the health professional ethically justified in overriding the parents’ wishes?’ We identified nine different ethical frameworks that were put forward by their authors as applicable across various ages and clinical scenarios. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Identification Before Prescription: Necessary Changes for the Support of Transgender Youth.Elizabeth R. Boskey & Jonathan M. Marron - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (2):78-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The harm threshold and parents’ obligation to benefit their children.Giles Birchley - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):123-126.
    In an earlier paper entitled _Harm is all you need?_, I used an analysis of English law to claim that the harm threshold was an unsuitable mediator of the best interests test when deciding if parental decisions should be overruled. In this paper I respond to a number of commentaries of that paper, and extend my discussion to consider the claim that the harm threshold gives appropriate normative weight to the interests of parents. While I accept that parents have some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Philosophical Feminist Bioethics.Herjeet Marway & Heather Widdows - 2015 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24 (2):165-174.
    Abstract:The end of the last century was a particularly vibrant period for feminist bioethics. Almost two decades on, we reflect on the legacy of the feminist critique of bioethics and investigate the extent to which it has been successful and what requires more attention yet. We do this by examining the past, present, and future: we draw out three feminist concerns that emerged in this period—abstraction, individualism, and power—and consider three feminist responses—relationality, particularity, and justice—and we finish with some thoughts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Children and Bioethics: Uses and Abuses of the Best-Interests Standard.L. M. Kopelman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):213-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Pubertal Suppression and Professional Obligations: May a Pediatric Endocrinologist Refuse to Treat an Adolescent With Gender Dysphoria?Armand Matheny Antommaria - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (1):43-46.
    Of the different features of this case, I focus on the pediatric endocrinologist's refusal to treat the patient. Providers generally have wide latitude in accepting or refusing patients. Appropriat...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Moral Status, Justice, and the Common Morality: Challenges for the Principlist Account of Moral Change.Kevin E. Hodges & Daniel P. Sulmasy - 2013 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23 (3):275-296.
    The idea that ethics can be derived from a common morality, while controversial, has become very influential in biomedical ethics. Although the concept is employed by several theories, it has most prominently been given a central role in principlism, an ethical theory endorsed by Tom Beauchamp and James Childress in Principles of Biomedical Ethics (2009).1 This text has become a cornerstone of medical ethics education, an achievement that has been commended by critics and supporters alike. It articulates a system of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Revisiting the Best Interest Standard: Uses and Misuses.Douglas S. Diekema - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):128-133.
    The best interest standard is the threshold most frequently employed by physicians and ethics consultants in challenging a parent’s refusal to provide consent for a child’s medical care. In this article, I will argue that the best interest standard has evolved to serve two different functions, and that these functions differ sufficiently that they require separate standards. While the best interest standard is appropriate for choosing among alternative treatment options for children, making recommendations to parents, and making decisions on behalf (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations