Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Essays on the active powers of the human mind.Thomas Reid - 2007 - In Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya, Late modern philosophy: essential readings with commentary. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 297-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Singular Terms and Intuitions In Kant’s Epistemology.Manley Thompson - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 26 (2):314 - 343.
    Kant's distinction between intuitive and discursive knowledge precludes his giving intuitions linguistic representation. Singular terms represent concepts given what kant calls a 'singular use' and are analyzable as definite descriptions. That the object described exists and that there is only one such object can be given linguistic representation only through an explicit assertion of existence and uniqueness. As an intuitionist in mathematics kant holds that mathematics proclaims the constructibility and not the existence of its objects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The Facts in Perception.Hermann Helmholtz - 1878 - In R. Kahl, Selected Writings of Hermann Helmholtz. Wesleyan University Press.
    The problems which that earlier period considered fundamental to all science were those of the theory of knowledge: What is true in our sense perceptions and thought? and In what way do our ideas correspond to reality? Philosophy and the natural sciences attack these questions from opposite directions, but they are the common problems of both. Philosophy, which is concerned with the mental aspect, endeavours to separate out whatever in our knowledge and ideas is due to the effects of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Kant's philosophy of arithmetic.Charles Parsons - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker, Kant on Pure Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Signs, Toy Models, and the A Priori.Lydia Patton - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (3):281-289.
    The Marburg neo-Kantians argue that Hermann von Helmholtz's empiricist account of the a priori does not account for certain knowledge, since it is based on a psychological phenomenon, trust in the regularities of nature. They argue that Helmholtz's account raises the 'problem of validity' (Gueltigkeitsproblem): how to establish a warranted claim that observed regularities are based on actual relations. I reconstruct Heinrich Hertz's and Ludwig Wittgenstein's Bild theoretic answer to the problem of validity: that scientists and philosophers can depict the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • I.—the origin and meaning of geometrical axioms.H. Helmholtz - 1876 - Mind 1 (3):301-321.
    The object in this article is to discuss the philosophical bearing of recent inquiries concerning geometrical axioms and the possibility of working out analytically other systems of geometry with other axioms than Euclid's. Digital edition compiled by Gabriele Dörflinger, Heidelberg University Library.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On Naturalizing Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Henry E. Allison - 1995 - Dialectica 49 (2‐4):335-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Force, law, and experiment: The evolution of helmholtz's philosophy of science.Michael Heidelberger - 1993 - In David Cahan, Hermann Von Helmholtz and the Foundations of Nineteenth-Century Science. University of California Press. pp. 461-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Über die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde.Arthur Schopenhauer & Christian Martin Julius Frauenstädt - 1970 - Hamburg,: Meiner. Edited by Michael Landmann & Elfriede Tielsch.
    Arthur Schopenhauer: Über die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde. Eine philosophische Abhandlung Schopenhauers Dissertation lag im Oktober 1813 der Philosophischen Fakultät der Universität Jena vor. Erstdruck: Rudolstadt 1813. Wiedergegeben wird der Text der 2. verbesserten Auflage, Frankfurt am Main 1847, in den spätere Herausgeber allerdings Zusätze integrierten, die sie Schopenhauers Handexemplaren und Manuskriptbüchern entnahmen. Sofern sich diese Zusätze nicht in den laufenden Text einfügen ließen, wurden sie in Fußnoten beigefügt. Diese Fußnoten werden hier gesondert gezählt und sind durch (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Helmholtz's Theory of Space and its Significance for Schlick.Matthias Neuber - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1):163 - 180.
    Helmholtz's theory of space had significant impact on Schlick's early ?critical realist? point of view. However, it will be argued in this paper that Schlick's appropriation of Helmholtz's ideas eventually lead to a rather radical transformation of the original Helmholtzian position.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • III. Kantian intuitions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1972 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 15 (1-4):341 – 345.
    By way of a reply to Charles Parsons's paper in the Nagel Festschrift, Kant's notion of intuition (Anschauung) is examined. It is argued that for Kant the immediate relation which an intuition has to its object is a mere corollary to its singularity. It does not presuppose (as Parsons suggests) any presence of the object to the mind. This is shown, e.g., by the Prolegomena § 8, where the objects of intuitions a priori are denied by Kant to be so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hermann von Helmholtz's Empirico-Transcendentalism Reconsidered: Construction and Constitution in Helmholtz's Psychology of the Object.Liesbet De Kock - 2014 - Science in Context 27 (4):709-744.
    ArgumentThis paper aims at contributing to the ongoing efforts to get a firmer grasp of the systematic significance of the entanglement of idealism and empiricism in Helmholtz's work. Contrary to existing analyses, however, the focal point of the present exposition is Helmholtz's attempt to articulate a psychological account of objectification. Helmholtz's motive, as well as his solution to the problem of the object are outlined, and interpreted against the background of his scientific practice on the one hand, and that of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From Helmholtz to Schlick: The evolution of the sign-theory of perception.Thomas Oberdan - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 52:35-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Helmholtz and classicism: The science of aesthetics and the aesthetics of science.Gary Hatfield - 1993 - In David Cahan, Hermann Von Helmholtz and the Foundations of Nineteenth-Century Science. University of California Press. pp. 522--58.
    This chapter examines the Helmholtz's changing conceptions of the relation between scientific cognition (the thought processes of the investigator) and artistic cognition. It begins with two case studies: Helmholtz's application of sensory physiology and psychology respectively to music and to painting. Consideration of these concrete cases leads to Helmholtz's account of the methodology of aesthetics, and specifically to his formulation of the distinction between the *Geisteswissenschaften* and *Naturwissenschaften*. It then examines the development of his comparative account of the thought processes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Absolute idealism and the rejection of Kantian dualism.Paul Guyer - 2000 - In Karl Ameriks, The Cambridge companion to German idealism. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 37--56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Intuition and Nature in Kant and Goethe.Jennifer Mensch - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 19 (3):431-453.
    Abstract: This essay addresses three specific moments in the history of the role played by intuition in Kant's system. Part one develops Kant's attitude toward intuition in order to understand how ‘sensible intuition’ becomes the first step in his development of transcendental idealism and how this in turn requires him to reject the possibility of an ‘intellectual intuition’ for human cognition. Part two considers the role of Jacobi when it came to interpreting both Kant's epistemic achievement and what were taken (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Helmholfz in seinem Verhältnis zu Kant.A. Biehl - 1904 - Kant Studien 9 (1-3):261-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant, Lonergan, and Fichte on the Critique of Immediacy and the Epistemology of Constraint in Human Knowing.Michael Baur - 2003 - International Philosophical Quarterly 43 (1):91-112.
    One of the defining characteristics of Kant’s “critical philosophy” is what has been called the “critique of immediacy” or the rejection of the “myth of the given.” According to the Kantian position, no object can count as an object for a human knower apart from the knower’s own activity or spontaneity. That is, no object can count as an object for a human knower on the basis of the object’s givenness alone. But this gives rise to a problem: how is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hermann Von Helmholtz and the new psychology.C. Stumpf - 1895 - Psychological Review 2 (1):1-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Voluntarism in early psychology: the case of Hermann von Helmholtz.Liesbet De Kock - 2014 - History of Psychology 17 (2):105-28.
    The failure to recognize the programmatic similarity between (post-)Kantian German philosophy and early psychology has impoverished psychology's historical self-understanding to a great extent. This article aims to contribute to recent efforts to overcome the gaps in the historiography of contemporary psychology, which are the result of an empiricist bias. To this end, we present an analysis of the way in which Hermann von Helmholtz's theory of perception resonates with Johann Gottlieb Fichte's Ego-doctrine. It will be argued that this indebtedness is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What Müller's Law of Specific Nerve Energies Says about the Mind.Howard Rachlin - 2005 - Behavior and Philosophy 33:41 - 54.
    Johannes Müller's law of specific nerve energies (LOSNE) states that the mind has access not to objects in the world but only to our nerves. This law implies that the contents of the mind have no qualities in common with environmental objects but serve only as arbitrary signs or markers of those objects. The present article traces the implications of LOSNE for non-physical theories of mind and for modern neural identity theory (that mental events are identical with their neurological representations) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations