Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Shmagency Question.Matthew Silverstein - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (5):1127-1142.
    Constitutivists hope to locate the foundations of ethics in the nature of action. They hope to find norms that are constitutive of agency. Recently David Enoch has argued that even if there are such norms, they cannot provide the last word when it comes to normativity, since they cannot tell us whether we have reason to be agents rather than shmagents. I argue that the force of the shmagency objection has been considerably overestimated, because philosophers on both sides of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Coming to terms with contingency : Humean constructivism about practical reason.Sharon Street - 2012 - In James Lenman & Yonatan Shemmer (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The problem of philosophical fundamental-grounding in light of a transcendental pragmatic of language.Karl -Otto Apel - 1975 - Man and World 8 (3):239-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reason and morality.Alan Gewirth - 1978 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    "Most modern philosophers attempt to solve the problem of morality from within the epistemological assumptions that define the dominant cultural perspective of our age. Alan Gewirth's Reason and Morality is a major work in this ongoing enterprise. Gewirth develops, with patience and skill, what he calls a 'modified naturalism' in which morality is derived by logic alone from the concept of action.... I think that the publication of Reason and Morality is a major event in the history of moral philosophy. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • The Second Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability.Stephen L. Darwall - 1996 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    The result is nothing less than a fundamental reorientation of moral theory that enables it at last to account for morality's supreme authority--an account that ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   585 citations  
  • The sources of normativity.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Onora O'Neill.
    Ethical concepts are, or purport to be, normative. They make claims on us: they command, oblige, recommend, or guide. Or at least when we invoke them, we make claims on one another; but where does their authority over us - or ours over one another - come from? Christine Korsgaard identifies four accounts of the source of normativity that have been advocated by modern moral philosophers: voluntarism, realism, reflective endorsement, and the appeal to autonomy. She traces their history, showing how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   774 citations  
  • On the meta-ethical status of constructivism: Reflections on G.A. Cohen's `facts and principles'.Miriam Ronzoni & Laura Valentini - 2008 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 7 (4):403-422.
    The Queen's College, Oxford, UK In his article `Facts and Principles', G.A. Cohen attempts to refute constructivist approaches to justification by showing that, contrary to what their proponents claim, fundamental normative principles are fact- in sensitive. We argue that Cohen's `fact-insensitivity thesis' does not provide a successful refutation of constructivism because it pertains to an area of meta-ethics which differs from the one tackled by constructivists. While Cohen's thesis concerns the logical structure of normative principles, constructivists ask how normative principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Agency, shmagency: Why normativity won't come from what is constitutive of action.David Enoch - 2006 - Philosophical Review 115 (2):169-198.
    There is a fairly widespread—and very infl uential—hope among philosophers interested in the status of normativity that the solution to our metaethical and, more generally, metanormative problems will emerge from the philosophy of action. In this essay, I will argue that these hopes are groundless. I will focus on the metanormative hope, but—as will become clear—showing that the solution to our metanormative problems will not come from what is constitutive of action will also devastate the hope of gaining significant insight (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Objective and unconditioned value.Rae Langton - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (2):157-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Autonomy and the Second Person Within: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall’s The Second‐Person Standpoint.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2007 - Ethics 118 (1):8-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Sources of Normativity.Christine Korsgaard - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196):384-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   686 citations  
  • Comment on Stephen Darwall's The Second Person Standpoint.Stephen Darwall - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):246-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reason and Morality.Adina Schwartz - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (4):654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • (1 other version)After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1753 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant's Formula of Humanity.Christine Korsgaard - 1986 - Kant Studien 77 (1-4):183-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Why Be an Agent?Evan Tiffany - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2):223 - 233.
    Constitutivism is the view that it is possible to derive contentful, normatively binding demands of practical reason and morality from the constitutive features of agency. Whereas much of the debate has focused on the constitutivist's ability to derive content, David Enoch has challenged her ability to generate normativity. Even if one can derive content from the constitutive aims of agency, one could simply demur: ?Bah! Agency, shmagency?. The ?Why be moral?? question would be replaced by the ?Why be an agent?? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Self-constitution: agency, identity, and integrity.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Agency and identity -- Necessitation -- Acts and actions -- Aristotle and Kant -- Agency and practical identity -- The metaphysics of normativity -- Constitutive standards -- The constitution of life -- In defense of teleology -- The paradox of self-constitution -- Formal and substantive principles of reason -- Formal versus substantive -- Testing versus weighing -- Maximizing and prudence -- Practical reason and the unity of the will -- The empiricist account of normativity -- The rationalist account of normativity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   500 citations  
  • Shmagency revisited.David Enoch - 2010 - In Michael Brady (ed.), New Waves in Metaethics. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    1. The Shmagency Challenge to Constitutivism In metaethics – and indeed, meta-normativity – constitutivism is a family of views that hope to ground normativity in norms, or standards, or motives, or aims that are constitutive of action and agency. And mostly because of the influential work of Christine Korsgaard and David Velleman, constitutivism seems to be gaining grounds in the current literature. The promises of constitutivism are significant. Perhaps chief among them are the hope to provide with some kind of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Korsgaard’s Private-Reasons Argument.Joshua Gert - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):303-324.
    In The Sources of Normativity, Christine Korsgaard presents and defends a neo-Kantian theory of normativity. Her initial account of reasons seems to make them dependent upon the practical identity of the agent, and upon the value the agent must place on her own humanity. This seems to make all reasons agent-relative. But Korsgaard claims that arguments similar to Wittgenstein’s private-language argument can show that reasons are in fact essentially agent-neutral. This paper explains both of Korsgaard’s Wittgensteinian arguments, and shows why (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reply to Korsgaard, Wallace, and Watson.Stephen Darwall - 2007 - Ethics 118 (1):52-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy.Bernard Williams - 1985 - Ethics 97 (4):821-833.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   928 citations  
  • (1 other version)Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians Ought to be Gewirthians.Deryck Beyleveld - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4):573-597.
    Christine Korsgaard claims that Gewirth’s argument for morality fails to demonstrate that there is a categorically binding principle on action because it operates with the assumption that reasons for action are essentially private. This attribution is unfounded and Korsgaard’s own argument for moral obligation, in its appeal to Wittgenstein’s Private Language Argument to establish that reasons for action are essentially public, is misdirected and unnecessary. Gewirth’s attempt to demonstrate a strictly a priori connection between a moral principle and the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Why Humean constructivists should become Kantian constructivists.Sem de Maagt - 2019 - Philosophical Explorations 22 (3):280-293.
    One of the main reasons for philosophers to have embraced Humean constructivism rather than Kantian constructivism is a negative one: they believe that in the end Kantian constructivism is an unsta...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)I. The Public use of Reason.Onora O'Neill - 1986 - Political Theory 14 (4):523-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians Ought to be Gewirthians.Deryck Beyleveld - 2015 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (5):573-597.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Skepticism about practical reason: Transcendental arguments and their limits.James Skidmore - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 109 (2):121-141.
    Transcendental arguments offer a particularlypowerful strategy for combating skepticism. Such arguments, after all, attempt to show thata particular skepticism is not simply mistakenbut inconsistent or self-refuting. Whilethus tempting to philosophers struggling withskepticism of various sorts, the boldconclusions of these arguments have longrendered them suspicious in the eyes of many. In fact, in a famous paper from 1968 BarryStroud develops what is often taken to be adecisive case against transcendental argumentsin general.Recent work in the area of practical reason,however, suggests that such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review of E thics and the Limits of Philosophy.Thomas Nagel - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (6):351-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant's Formula of Humanity.Ch M. Korsgaard - 1986 - Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 77 (2):183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Considerations on the Notion of Moral Validity in the Moral Theories of Kant and Habermas.Pablo Gilabert - 2006 - Kant Studien 97 (2):210-227.
    In what follows I will consider Kant's and Habermas's conceptions of moral validity in a comparative and critical way. First, I will reconstruct Habermas's discursive or deliberative reformulation of Kant's moral theory. And, second, I will introduce some comparative critical considerations. I will contend that, though much is gained with Habermas's intersubjectivist reformulation of Kant's moral philosophy, some problems emerge that could be treated with the help of certain Kantian insights. I will focus on Kant's and Habermas's strictly moral writings. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Williams' False Dilemma: How to Give Categorically Binding Impartial Reasons to Real Agents.Deryck Beyleveld - 2013 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (2):204-226.
    According to Bernard Williams, attempts to justify a categorically binding impartial principle fail because they can only establish categorically binding requirements on action by making them non-universalizable , and can only establish impartial requirements by rendering them inapplicable to real agents . But, an individual cannot be the particular agent the individual is without being an agent every bit as much as an individual cannot be an agent without being the particular agent that the individual is. On this basis, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The publicity of reasons.R. Jay Wallace - 2009 - Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1):471-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The grounds of ethical judgement: new transcendental arguments in moral philosophy.Christian Illies - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Is it merely a matter of taste or convention to consider something right or wrong? Or can we find good reasons for our values and judgements that are independent of culture and tradition? The problem is as old as philosophy itself; and after more than two millennia of scholarly debate, there seems no end to the controversy. But Christian Illies suggests that powerful new forms of transcendental argument (a philosophical tool known since antiquity) may offer a long-sought cornerstone for morality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The substantive dimension of deliberative practical rationality.Pablo Gilabert - 2005 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 31 (2):185-210.
    The aim of this paper is to propose a model for understanding the relation between substance and procedure in discourse ethics and deliberative democracy capable of answering the common charge that they involve an ‘empty formalism’. The expressive-elaboration model introduced here answers this concern by arguing that the deliberative practical rationality presupposed by discourse ethics and deliberative democracy involves the creation of a practical medium in which certain general basic ideas of solidarity, equality and freedom are expressed and elaborated in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Korsgaard, Wittgenstein, and the Mafioso.Mark LeBar - 2001 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):261-271.
    Response-dependent accounts of value claim that to understand what we are saying about the objects of our value judgments, we must take into account the responses those objects provoke. Recent discussions of the proposal that value is response-dependent are obscured by dogmas about response-dependence, that (1) response-dependency must be known a priori, (2) must hold necessarily, and (3) the terms involved must designate rigidly. These “dogmas” stand in the way of formulating and assessing a clear conception of value as response-dependent. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A substantivist construal of discourse ethics.Pablo Gilabert - 2005 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 13 (3):405 – 437.
    This paper presents a substantivist construal of discourse ethics, which claims that we should see our engagement in public deliberation as expressing and elaborating a substantive commitment to basic moral ideas of solidarity, equality, and freedom. This view is different from Habermas's standard formalist defence of discourse ethics, which attempts to derive the principle of discursive moral justification from primarily non-moral presuppositions of rational argumentation as such. After explicating the difference between the substantivist and the formalist construal, I defend the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Morality.Alan Gewirth - 1968 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 170 (4):444-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Precis: The second-person standpoint. [REVIEW]Stephen Darwall - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):216-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Problem of Philosophical Fundamental-Grounding in Light of a Transcendental Pragmatic of Language.Karl-Otto Apel - 1975 - Man and World 8 (3):239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Morality.Alan Gewirth - 1968 - Philosophy 56 (216):266-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Constructivist Practical Reasoning and Objectivity.Melissa Barry - 2013 - In David Archard, Monique Deveaux, Neil Manson & Daniel Weinstock (eds.), Reading Onora o’Neill. New York: Routledge. pp. 17-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations