Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Ethical Grounds for the Best Interest of the Child.Lynne Bowyer - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (1):63-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):5-20.
    It is my view that one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's will. Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call "first-order desires" or "desires of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1458 citations  
  • Thinking about the good: Reconfiguring liberal metaphysics (or not) for people with cognitive disabilities.Anita Silvers & Leslie Pickering Francis - 2009 - Metaphilosophy 40 (3-4):475-498.
    Liberalism welcomes diversity in substantive ideas of the good but not in the process whereby these ideas are formed. Ideas of the good acquire weight on the presumption that each is a person's own, formed independently. But people differ in their capacities to conceptualize. Some, appropriately characterized as cerebral, are proficient in and profoundly involved with conceptualizing. Others, labeled cognitively disabled, range from individuals with mild limitations to those so unable to express themselves that we cannot be sure whether their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • What is a child?Tamar Schapiro - 1999 - Ethics 109 (4):715–738.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Children, Paternalism and the Development of Autonomy.Amy Mullin - 2014 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (3):413-426.
    This paper addresses the issue of paternalism in child-rearing. Since the parent–child relationship seems to be the linguistic source of the concept, one may be tempted to assume that raising a child represents a particularly appropriate sphere for paternalism. The parent–child relationship is generally understood as a relationship that is supposed to promote the development and autonomy-formation of the child, so that the apparent source of the concept is a form of autonomy-oriented paternalism. Far from taking paternalism to be overtly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The child's right to an open future?Claudia Mills - 2003 - Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (4):499–509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Feinberg, Mills, and the child's right to an open future.Mianna Lotz - 2006 - Journal of Social Philosophy 37 (4):537–551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Parental Autonomy.John Bigelow, John Campbell, Susan M. Dodds, Robert Pargetter, Elizabeth W. Prior & Robert Young - 1988 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 5 (2):183-196.
    ABSTRACT We argue that in societies like our own the prevailing view that parents have both special responsibilities for and special rights over their children fails to give a proper understanding of the autonomy both of parents and of children. It is our claim that there is a logical priority of the separable interests of a child over the autonomy of its parents in the fulfilment of their special responsibilities for and the exercise of their special rights over their children. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Acting freely.Gerald Dworkin - 1970 - Noûs 4 (4):367-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations