Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Spinoza on Final Causality.John Carriero - 2005 - In Daniel Garber & Steven Nadler (eds.), Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy Volume 2. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Introduction.Eileen O’Neill - 2019 - In Eileen O’Neill & Marcy P. Lascano (eds.), Feminist History of Philosophy: The Recovery and Evaluation of Women’s Philosophical Thought. Springer, NM 87747, USA: Springer. pp. 1-20.
    This Introduction examines the role that feminism has played in the recovery and evaluation of women’s philosophical writings. First, O’Neill addresses the question of whether it is possible to trace conceptions of feminism before the twentieth or nineteenth century. O’Neill offers no analysis of ‘feminism,’ but instead, argues that certain components of feminism that may be traced back to Christine de Pizan. O’Neill then argues that how we understand the role of women in our histories depends on the methodology one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Reason and Freedom: Margaret Cavendish on the order and disorder of nature.Karen Detlefsen - 2007 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89 (2):157-191.
    According to Margaret Cavendish the entire natural world is essentially rational such that everything thinks in some way or another. In this paper, I examine why Cavendish would believe that the natural world is ubiquitously rational, arguing against the usual account, which holds that she does so in order to account for the orderly production of very complex phenomena (e.g. living beings) given the limits of the mechanical philosophy. Rather, I argue, she attributes ubiquitous rationality to the natural world in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Atomism, Monism, and Causation in the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish.Karen Detlefsen - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3:199-240.
    Between 1653 and 1655 Margaret Cavendish makes a radical transition in her theory of matter, rejecting her earlier atomism in favour of an infinitely-extended and infinitely-divisible material plenum, with matter being ubiquitously self-moving, sensing, and rational. It is unclear, however, if Cavendish can actually dispense of atomism. One of her arguments against atomism, for example, depends upon the created world being harmonious and orderly, a premise Cavendish herself repeatedly undermines by noting nature’s many disorders. I argue that her supposed difficulties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Systematic Divergences in Malebranche and Cudworth.David Cunning - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):343-363.
    : For Cudworth, God would be a drudge if He did each and every thing, and so the universe contains plastic natures. Malebranche argues that finite power is unintelligible and thus that God does do each and every thing. The supremacy of God is reflected in the range of His activity and also in the manner of His activity: He acts by general non-composite volitions. Malebranche (like Cudworth) is careful to adjust other aspects of his system to square with his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Observations upon Experimental Philosophy.Margaret Cavendish & Eileen O'neill - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214):175-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Aristotle on teleology.Monte Ransome Johnson - 2008 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Monte Johnson examines one of the most controversial aspects of Aristiotle's natural philosophy: his teleology. Is teleology about causation or explanation? Does it exclude or obviate mechanism, determinism, or materialism? Is it focused on the good of individual organisms, or is god or man the ultimate end of all processes and entities? Is teleology restricted to living things, or does it apply to the cosmos as a whole? Does it identify objectively existent causes in the world, or is it merely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Women Philosophers of the Seventeenth Century.Jacqueline Broad - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In this rich and detailed study of early modern women's thought, Jacqueline Broad explores the complexity of women's responses to Cartesian philosophy and its intellectual legacy in England and Europe. She examines the work of thinkers such as Mary Astell, Elisabeth of Bohemia, Margaret Cavendish, Anne Conway and Damaris Masham, who were active participants in the intellectual life of their time and were also the respected colleagues of philosophers such as Descartes, Leibniz and Locke. She also illuminates the continuities between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought.Marleen Rozemond & Dennis des Chene - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (2):330.
    In recent years more and more scholars of early modern philosophy have come to acknowledge that our understanding of Descartes’s thought benefits greatly from consideration of his intellectual background. Research in this direction has taken off, but much work remains to be done. Dennis Des Chene offers a major contribution to this enterprise. This erudite book is the result of a very impressive body of research into a number of late Aristotelian scholastics, some fairly well known, such as Suárez, others (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Descartes and occasional causation.Steven Nadler - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (1):35 – 54.
    After a brief analysis of the nature of occasional causation, distinguishing it from both efficient causation and the doctrine of occasionalism, it is argued that this model of causation informs Descartes' account of the generation of sensory ideas in the mind. It is further argued that, consequently, Descartes is not an occasionalist on this matter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Margaret Cavendish's Epistemology.Kourken Michaelian - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (1):31 – 53.
    This paper provides a systematic reconstruction of Cavendish's general epistemology and a characterization of the fundamental role of that theory in her natural philosophy. After reviewing the outlines of her natural philosophy, I describe her treatment of 'exterior knowledge', i.e. of perception in general and of sense perception in particular. I then describe her treatment of 'interior knowledge', i.e. of self-knowledge and 'conception'. I conclude by drawing out some implications of this reconstruction for our developing understanding of Cavendish's natural philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aristotle, teleology, and reduction.Susan Sauvé Meyer - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):791-825.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Boyle's Conception of Nature.J. E. McGuire - 1972 - Journal of the History of Ideas 33 (4):523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The philosophical innovations of Margaret Cavendish.Susan James - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (2):219 – 244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Physiologia: natural philosophy in late Aristotelian and Cartesian thought.Dennis Des Chene - 1996 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Physiologia provides an accessible and comprehensive guide to late Aristotelian natural philosophy; with that context in hand, it offers new interpretations of major themes in Descartes’s natural philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Whatever is, is God" : substance and things in Spinoza's metaphysics.Steven Nadler - 2008 - In Charles Huenemann (ed.), Interpreting Spinoza: Critical Essays. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Spinoza on final causality.John Carriero - 2005 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 2:105-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Two Opponents of Material Atomism: Cavendish and Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 2007 - In P. Phemister & S. Brown (eds.), Leibniz and the English-Speaking World. Springer. pp. 35-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Mechanist-Vitalist Soul of Margaret Cavendish.Jay Stevenson - 1996 - Studies in English Literature 36:527-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Margaret Cavendish and Henry More.Sarah Hutton - 2003 - In Stephen Clucas (ed.), A Princely Brave Woman: Essays on Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle. Ashgate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • In Dialogue with Thomas Hobbes: Margaret Cavendish’s Natural Philosophy.Sarah Hutton - 1996 - Women’s Writing 4:421-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cavendish on the Intelligibility of the Prospect of Thinking Matter.David Cunning - 2006 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (2):117 - 136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton.Robert Hugh Kargon - 1967 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (2):160-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Teleology in Spinoza and early modern rationalism.Don Garret - 1999 - In Gennaro Rocco & Huenemann Charles (eds.), New Essays on the Rationalists. Oxford University Press. pp. 310--36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations