Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Moral Obligation to Create Children with the Best Chance of the Best Life.Julian Savulescu & Guy Kahane - 2008 - Bioethics 23 (5):274-290.
    According to what we call the Principle of Procreative Beneficence, couples who decide to have a child have a significant moral reason to select the child who, given his or her genetic endowment, can be expected to enjoy the most well-being. In the first part of this paper, we introduce PB, explain its content, grounds, and implications, and defend it against various objections. In the second part, we argue that PB is superior to competing principles of procreative selection such as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Clarifying substituted judgement: the endorsed life approach: Table 1.John Phillips & David Wendler - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (9):723-730.
    A primary goal of clinical practice is to respect patient autonomy. To promote this goal for patients who have lost the ability to make their own decisions, commentators recommend that surrogates make their treatment decisions based on the substituted judgment standard. This standard is commonly interpreted as directing surrogates to make the decision the patient would have made in the circumstances, if the patient were competent. However, recent commentators have argued that this approach—attempting to make the decision the patient would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Families, Friends, and Special Obligations.Diane Jeske - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):527 - 555.
    Most of us accept that we have special obligations to our family members: to, e.g., our parents, our siblings, and our grandparents. But it is extremely difficult to offer a plausible grounding for such obligations, given the apparent fact that familial relationships are not voluntarily entered. I did not choose to be my mother's daughter or my brother's sister, so why suppose that such facts about me are morally significant? Why suppose that I owe more to my mother or to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Procreative beneficence – cui Bono?Jakob Elster - 2009 - Bioethics 25 (9):482-488.
    Recently, Julian Savulescu and Guy Kahane have defended the Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PB), according to which prospective parents ought to select children with the view that their future child has ‘the best chance of the best life’. I argue that the arguments Savulescu and Kahane adduce in favour of PB equally well support what I call the Principle of General Procreative Beneficence (GPB). GPB states that couples ought to select children in view of maximizing the overall expected value in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On the partiality of procreative beneficence: a critical note.Thomas Søbirk Petersen - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (9):771-774.
    The aim of this paper is to criticise the well-discussed Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PB) lately refined by Julian Savulescu and Guy Kahane. First, it is argued that advocates of PB leave us with an implausible justification for the moral partiality towards the child (or children) reproducers decide to bring into existence as compared with all other individuals. This is implausible because the reasons given in favour of the partiality of PB, which are based on practical reason and common-sense morality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Parental reasoning about growth attenuation therapy: report of a single-case study.Nicola Kerruish & John R. McMillan - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (9):745-749.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations