Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. No Work for a Theory of Grounding.Jessica M. Wilson - 2014 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 (5-6):535-579.
    It has recently been suggested that a distinctive metaphysical relation— ‘Grounding’—is ultimately at issue in contexts in which some goings-on are said to hold ‘in virtue of’’, be ‘metaphysically dependent on’, or be ‘nothing over and above’ some others. Grounding is supposed to do good work in illuminating metaphysical dependence. I argue that Grounding is also unsuited to do this work. To start, Grounding alone cannot do this work, for bare claims of Grounding leave open such basic questions as whether (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   398 citations  
  • (1 other version)Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy.John Rawls - 2000 - Critica 35 (104):121-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   200 citations  
  • The unimportance of Kant's highest good.Thomas Auxter - 1979 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 17 (2):121-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Grounding: Toward a Theory of the I n-Virtue-Of Relation.Paul Audi - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy 109 (12):685-711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   322 citations  
  • Autonomy and the highest good.Lara Denis - 2005 - Kantian Review 10:33-59.
    Kant’s ethics conceives of rational beings as autonomous–capable of legislating the moral law, and of motivating themselves to act out of respect for that law. Kant’s ethics also includes a notion of the highest good, the union of virtue with happiness proportional to, and consequent on, virtue. According to Kant, morality sets forth the highest good as an object of the totality of all things good as ends. Much about Kant’s conception of the highest good is controversial. This paper focuses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Moral Paragons and the Metaphysics of Morals.Marcia Baron - 2006 - In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 335–349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Humanity as an Idea, as an Ideal, and as an End in Itself.Richard Dean - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):171-195.
    Kant emphasizes that moral philosophy must be divided into two parts, a metaphysics of morals, and an empirical application to individuals, which Kant calls 'moral anthropology'. But Kant gives humanity (die Menschheit) a prominent role even in the purely rational part of ethics – for example, one formulation of the categorical imperative is a demand to treat humanity as an end in itself. This paper argues that the only concepts of humanity suited to play such a role are the rational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Categorical Imperative.Stuart M. Brown & H. J. Paton - 1949 - Philosophical Review 58 (6):599 - 611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Plato and the Metaphysics of Purpose.David A. White - 1993 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 10:67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • I. Kant after virtue.Onora O'Neill - 1983 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):387 – 405.
    Maclntyre's refurbishing of Aristotelian ethics aims to restore both intelligibility and rationality to moral discourse. In After Virtue he concentrates on showing how intelligible action requires that lives be led within institutional and cultural traditions. But he does not offer a developed account of practical reason which could provide grounds for seeking some rather than other intelligible continuations of lives and traditions. Despite Maclntyre's criticisms of Kant's ethics, a Kantian account of practical reasoning may complement his account of intelligibility. An (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kant's conception of the highest good as immanent and transcendent.John R. Silber - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (4):469-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Kant's Highest Good: Albatross, Keystone, Achilles Heel.Lance Simmons - 1993 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 10 (4):355 - 368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason.L. W. BECK - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 19 (3):438-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • In Defense of Kant's Religion.Chris L. Firestone & Nathan Jacobs - 2009 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 66 (3):167-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves.Onora O’Neill - 1989 - The Monist 72 (3):341-361.
    Kant’s Groundwork is the most read and surely the most exasperating of his works on practical philosophy. Both its structure and its arguments remain obscure and controversial. A quick list of unsettled questions reminds one how much is in doubt. The list might include the following: Why does Kant shift the framework of his discussion three times in a short work? Does he establish that there is a supreme principle of morality? Does he show that the Categorical Imperative is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations