Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)The Concept of Representation.Hanna Fenichel Pitkin - 1967 - University of California Press.
    Being concerned with representation, this book is about an idea, a concept, a word. It is primarily a conceptual analysis, not a historical study of the way in which representative government has evolved, nor yet an empirical investigation of the behavior of contemporary representatives or the expectations voters have about them. Yet, although the book is about a word, it is not about mere words, not merely about words. For the social philosopher, for the social scientist, words are not "mere"; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • The Concept of Representation.Hanna Fenichel Pitkin - 1974 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 7 (2):128-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • (1 other version)Children: Rights and Childhood (3rd edition).David Archard - 2014 - Routledge.
    Children: Rights and Childhood is widely regarded as the first book to offer a detailed philosophical examination of children’s rights. David Archard provides a clear and accessible introduction to a topic that has assumed increasing relevance since the book’s first publication. -/- The third edition has been fully revised and updated throughout with a new chapter providing an in-depth analysis of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) and Part 2 has been restructured to move the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • The child's status in the democratic state.Francis Schrag - 1975 - Political Theory 3 (4):441-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • 13 Commission for Future Generations in the Knesset: lessons learnt.Shlomo Shoham & Nira Lamay - 2006 - In Tremmel J. (ed.), The Handbook of Intergenerational Justice. Edward Elgar. pp. 244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Democracy in Time: Popular Sovereignty and Temporal Representation.Dennis F. Thompson - 2005 - Constellations 12 (2):245-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Representation as Advocacy.Nadia Urbinati - 2000 - Political Theory 28 (6):758-786.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Disfranchisement of the Elderly, and Other Attempts to Secure Intergenerational Justice.Philippe van Parijs - 1998 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (4):292-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • The Concept of Representation.D. A. Lloyd Thomas - 1969 - Philosophical Quarterly 19 (75):186-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Précis of Democratic Autonomy.Henry S. Richardson - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1):187–195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • A "selection model" of political representation.Jane Mansbridge - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (4):369-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • No Playing in the Public Sphere.Jessica Kulynych - 2001 - Social Theory and Practice 27 (2):231-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • [Book review] democratic justice. [REVIEW]Ian Shapiro - 2001 - Social Theory and Practice 27 (3):519-534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • A fiduciary theory of jus cogens.Evan J. Criddle & Evan Fox-Decent - unknown
    For several decades, international law has recognized certain norms such as the prohibitions against genocide, slavery, and military aggression as "jus cogens"- peremptory law which supersedes conflicting international treaties and customs. Despite widespread acceptance of the jus cogens concept, legal theorists continue to debate whether peremptory norms derive their legal authority from state consent, natural law, or the demands of international public order. Anxiety over peremptory norms' legal basis has frustrated efforts to clarify the scope and content of jus cogens, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why Citizenship: Where, When and How Children?Ruth Lister - 2007 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 8 (2):693-718.
    This Article addresses the general question of "why citizenship?" through the lens of children’s citizenship. It unpacks the different elements of substantive citizenship and considers what they mean for children: membership and participation; rights; responsibilities; and equality of status, respect and recognition. It then discusses the lessons that may be learned from feminist critiques of mainstream constructions of citizenship, paying particular attention to the question of capacity for citizenship. It concludes by suggesting that much of the literature that is making (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Representation and Waldron's Objection to Judicial Review.Dimitrios Kyritsis - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (4):733-751.
    Jeremy Waldron objects to judicial review of legislation on the ground that it effectively accords the views of a few judges ‘superior voting weight’ to those of ordinary citizens. This objection overlooks that representative government does the same. This article explores the concept of political representation and argues that delegates may be institutionally bound to heed the convictions of their constituents, but they are not their proxies. Rather, they are best viewed as their trustees. They ought to decide according to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The fiduciary constitution of human rights: Evan fox-decent and Evan J. criddle.Evan Fox-Decent - 2009 - Legal Theory 15 (4):301-336.
    We argue that human rights are best conceived as norms arising from a fiduciary relationship that exists between states and the citizens and noncitizens subject to their power. These norms draw on a Kantian conception of moral personhood, protecting agents from instrumentalization and domination. They do not, however, exist in the abstract as timeless natural rights. Instead, they are correlates of the state's fiduciary duty to provide equal security under the rule of law, a duty that flows from the state's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Disfranchisement of the Elderly, and Other Attempts to Secure Intergenerational Justice.Philippe Van Parijs - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (4):292-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Children and democracy: Theory and policy.Francis Schrag - 2004 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 3 (3):365-379.
    This article identifies four approaches to arguing for democracy, showing that none has an adequate way of supporting both full adult inclusion and the exclusion of children. I focus in Section 2 on the arguments of David Estlund and Thomas Christiano, showing that their arguments against guardianship call into question the exclusion of children from the franchise. In Section 3, I explain why the exclusion of children constitutes an injustice, and in the final section, I consider two approaches to remedying (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Representation and waldrons objection to judicial review.Kyritsis Dimitrios - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (4).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation