Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Analytical symbols and geometrical figures in eighteenth-century calculus.Giovanni Ferraro - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 32 (3):535-555.
    Leibnizian-Newtonian calculus was a theory that dealt with geometrical objects; the figure continued to play one of the fundamental roles it had played in Greek geometry: it susbstituted a part of reasoning. During the eighteenth century a process of de-geometrization of calculus took place, which consisted in the rejection of the use of diagrams and in considering calculus as an 'intellectual' system where deduction was merely linguistic and mediated. This was achieved by interpreting variables as universal quantities and introducing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Tractional Motion and the Legitimation of Transcendental Curves.H. J. M. Bos - 1988 - Centaurus 31 (1):9-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The foundational aspects of Gauss’s work on the hypergeometric, factorial and digamma functions.Giovanni Ferraro - 2007 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61 (5):457-518.
    In his writings about hypergeometric functions Gauss succeeded in moving beyond the restricted domain of eighteenth-century functions by changing several basic notions of analysis. He rejected formal methodology and the traditional notions of functions, complex numbers, infinite numbers, integration, and the sum of a series. Indeed, he thought that analysis derived from a few, intuitively given notions by means of other well-defined concepts which were reducible to intuitive ones. Gauss considered functions to be relations between continuous variable quantities while he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The calculus as algebraic analysis: Some observations on mathematical analysis in the 18th century.Craig G. Fraser - 1989 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 (4):317-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions and his ideal of purity of method.Marco Panza & Giovanni Ferraro - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (2):95-197.
    We reconstruct essential features of Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions by exhibiting its structure and basic assumptions, as well as its main shortcomings. We explain Lagrange’s notions of function and algebraic quantity, and we concentrate on power-series expansions, on the algorithm for derivative functions, and the remainder theorem—especially on the role this theorem has in solving geometric and mechanical problems. We thus aim to provide a better understanding of Enlightenment mathematics and to show that the foundations of mathematics did not, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Arguments on motivation in the rise and decline of a mathematical theory; the?construction of equations?, 1637?ca.1750.H. J. M. Bos - 1984 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 30 (3-4):331-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations