Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Trade, Plantations, and Property: John Locke and the Economic Defense of Colonialism.Barbara Arneil - 1994 - Journal of the History of Ideas 55 (4):591-609.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The long goodbye: Hugo Grotius’ justification of Dutch expansion overseas, 1615–1645.Martine Julia van Ittersum - 2010 - History of European Ideas 36 (4):386-411.
    This article examines Grotius’ lifelong support for Dutch expansion overseas. As noted in other publications of mine, Grotius cooperated closely with the directors of the Dutch East India Company (VOC) in the years 1604–1615. Right up to his arrest for high treason in August 1618, he contributed towards Dutch government discussions about the establishment of a West India Company (WIC). Three years of imprisonment at Loevestein Castle and, following his escape, long years of exile could not weaken his dedication to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What's Wrong with Colonialism.Lea Ypi - 2013 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 41 (2):158-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Sharing Mother Nature's Gifts: A Reply to Quong and Miller.Hillel Steiner - 2011 - Journal of Political Philosophy 19 (1):110-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Left-Libertarianism: A Primer.Peter Vallentyne - 2000 - In Peter Vallentyne & Hillel Steiner (eds.), Left Libertarianism and Its Critics: The Contemporary Debate. Palgrave Publishers.
    Left-libertarian theories of justice hold that agents are full self-owners and that natural resources are owned in some egalitarian manner. Unlike most versions of egalitarianism, leftlibertarianism endorses full self-ownership, and thus places specific limits on what others may do to one’s person without one’s permission. Unlike the more familiar right-libertarianism (which also endorses full self-ownership), it holds that natural resources—resources which are not the results of anyone's choices and which are necessary for any form of activity—may be privately appropriated only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Historical rights and fair shares.A. John Simmons - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (2):149 - 184.
    My aim of this paper is to clarify, and in a certain very limited way to defend, historical theories of property rights (and their associated theories of social or distributive justice). It is important, I think, to better understand historical rights for several reasons: first, because of the extent to which historical theories capture commonsense, unphilosophical views about property and justice; then, because historical theories have fallen out of philosophical fashion, and are consequently not much scrutinized anymore; and finally, because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Superseding historic injustice.Jeremy Waldron - 1992 - Ethics 103 (1):4-28.
    Analyzes the historic correlation of injustice and moral judgments. Universalizability in analyzing moral judgments; Role of payment of money in the embodiment of communal remembrance; Symbolic reparation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • The Taking of Territory and the Wrongs of Colonialism.Margaret Moore - 2018 - Journal of Political Philosophy 27 (1):87-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Settlement, expulsion, and return.Anna Stilz - 2017 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 16 (4):351-374.
    This article discusses two normative questions raised by cases of colonial settlement. First, is it sometimes wrong to migrate and settle in a previously inhabited land? If so, under what conditions? Second, should settler countries ever take steps to undo wrongful settlement, by enforcing repatriation and return? The article argues that it is wrong to settle in another country in cases where one comes with intent to colonize the population against their will, or one possesses an adequate territorial base somewhere (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • IX.—Essentially Contested Concepts.W. B. Gallie - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):167-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  • Exploitation and disadvantage.Benjamin Ferguson - 2016 - Economics and Philosophy 32 (3):485-509.
    According to some accounts of exploitation, most notably Ruth Sample’s degradation-based account and Robert Goodin’s vulnerability-based account, exploitation occurs when an advantaged party fails to constrain their advantage in light of another’s disadvantage, regardless of the cause of this disadvantage. Because the duty of constraint in these accounts does not depend on the cause of the disadvantage, the advantaged’s duty of constraint is what I call a ‘come-what-may’ duty. I show that come-what-may duties create moral hazards that can themselves be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the Distinctive Procedural Wrong of Colonialism.Laura Valentini - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (4):312-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Nations, States, and Territory.Anna Stilz - 2011 - Ethics 121 (3):572-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Territorial Sovereignty.Anna Stilz & Christine Hobden - 2020 - Theoria 67 (163):82-105.
    18 November 2019CH: Thank you for agreeing to do this. The prompt for the interview was to talk about your recently published book, Territorial Sovereignty, but I thought before we got into that you could say something about your earlier work and how that led you to be interested in this particular project that you deal with in the book.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Can libertarians get away with fraud?Benjamin Ferguson - 2018 - Economics and Philosophy 34 (2):165-184.
    :In this paper I argue that libertarianism neither prohibits exchanges in which consent is gained through deceit, nor does it entail that such exchanges are morally invalid. However, contra James Child’s similar claim, that it is incapable of delivering these verdicts, I argue that libertarianscanclaim that exchanges involving deceitfully obtained consent are morally invalid by appealing to an external theory of moral permissibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Self-ownership and equality: a lockean reconciliation.Michael Otsuka - 1998 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (1):65-92.
    I thank the members of the Law and Philosophy Discussion Group in Los Angeles and those who attended a talk sponsored by the philosophy department at New York University, where I presented earlier versions of this paper. I would also like to thank G. A. Cohen, Stephen Munzer, Seana Shiffrin, Peter Vallentyne, Andrew Williams, and the editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs, who read and provided written commentary on earlier drafts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • John Locke, Carolina, and the Two Treatises of Government.David Armitage - 2004 - Political Theory 32 (5):602-627.
    Recent scholarship on John Locke’s Two Treatises of Government has drawn particular attention to the colonial antecedents and applications of the theory of appropriation in chapter V of theSecond Treatise. This attention has coincided with a more general interest among political theorists in the historical and theoretical relationship between liberalism and colonialism. This essay reviews the surviving evidence for Locke’s knowledge of the Carolina colony and argues that it was both more extensive and more enduring than previous commentators have suggested. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Do territorial rights include the right to exclude?Cara Nine - 2019 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 18 (4):307-322.
    Do territorial rights include the right to exclude? This claim is often assumed to be true in territorial rights theory. And if this claim is justified, a state may have a prima facie right to unil...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Justice and Colonialism.Margaret Moore - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (8):447-461.
    This paper examines the relationship between justice and colonialism. It defines colonialism; examines the kind of injustice that colonialism involved; and the possibility of corrective justice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Natural Resources, Territorial Right, and Global Distributive Justice.Margaret Moore - 2012 - Political Theory 40 (1):84-107.
    The current statist order assumes that states have a right to make rules involving the transfer and/or extraction of natural resources within the territory. Cosmopolitan theories of global justice have questioned whether the state is justified in its control over natural resources, typically by pointing out that having resources is a matter of good luck, and this unfairness should be addressed. This paper argues that self-determination does generate a right over resources, which others should not interfere with. It does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Decolonization and self-determination.Anna Stilz - 2015 - Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (1):1-24.
    Abstract:While self-determination is a cardinal principle of international law, its meaning is often obscure. Yet international law clearly recognizes decolonization as a central application of the principle. Most ordinary people also agree that the liberation of colonial peoples was a moral triumph. This essay examines three philosophical theories of self-determination’s value, and asks which one best captures the reasons why decolonization was morally required. The instrumentalist theory holds that decolonization was required because subject peoples were unjustly governed, the democratic view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Territorial Rights and Exclusion.Lea Ypi - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (3):241-253.
    Is it possible to justify territorial rights? Provided a justification for territorial rights can be found, does it ground claims toparticularterritories? And provided a claim to particular territories can be justified, what kind of claim is it? Is it a claim to jurisdiction? A claim to control resources? A claim to control the movement of people across borders? In this paper I review some prominent accounts seeking to answer these questions. After outlining their main features, I focus on some difficulties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Territorial boundaries and history.Anna Stilz - 2019 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 18 (4):374-385.
    This article evaluates the theory of boundary legitimacy put forward in A John Simmons’s recent book Boundaries of Authority. I believe Simmons is correct to hold that questions about the legitimac...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Territorial Dimension of Self‐Determination.Margaret Moore - 1998 - In National Self-Determination and Secession. Oxford University Press.
    This chapter examines one of the most serious problems with the principle of self‐determination, viz., that this concept does not tell us who the peoples are that are entitled to self‐determination or the jurisdictional unit that they are entitled. It examines indigenous, historical, superior culture, and occupancy arguments for rights to a particular territory and suggests normative principles for thinking about jurisdictional units.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Property and Territory: Locke, Kant, and Steiner.David Miller - 2010 - Journal of Political Philosophy 19 (1):90-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The long goodbye: Hugo Grotius’ justification of Dutch expansion overseas, 1615–1645.Martine van Ittersum - 2010 - History of European Ideas 36 (4):386-411.
    This article examines Grotius’ lifelong support for Dutch expansion overseas. As noted in other publications of mine, Grotius cooperated closely with the directors of the Dutch East India Company (VOC) in the years 1604–1615. Right up to his arrest for high treason in August 1618, he contributed towards Dutch government discussions about the establishment of a West India Company (WIC). Three years of imprisonment at Loevestein Castle and, following his escape, long years of exile could not weaken his dedication to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Territorial Rights.Tamar Meisels - 2005 - Law and Philosophy 72 (1):1-11.
    Liberal defences of nationalism have become prevalent since the mid-1980 s. Curiously, they have largely neglected the fact that nationalism is primarily about land. Should liberals throw up their hands in despair when confronting conflicting claims stemming from incommensurable national narratives and holy texts? Should they dismiss conflicting demands that stem solely from particular cultures, religions and mythologies in favour of a supposedly neutral set of guidelines? Does history matter? Should ancient injustices interest us today? Should we care who reached (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations