Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Thomas S. Kuhn.Mary Hesse - 1963 - Isis 54 (2):286-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Re-orienting discussions of scientific explanation: A functional perspective.Andrea I. Woody - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 52 (C):79-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions by Thomas S. Kuhn. [REVIEW]Mary Hesse - 1963 - Isis 54:286-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Four Decades of Scientific Explanation.Wesley C. Salmon & Anne Fagot-Largeault - 1989 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 16 (2):355.
    As Aristotle stated, scientific explanation is based on deductive argument--yet, Wesley C. Salmon points out, not all deductive arguments are qualified explanations. The validity of the explanation must itself be examined. _Four Decades of Scientific Explanation_ provides a comprehensive account of the developments in scientific explanation that transpired in the last four decades of the twentieth century. It continues to stand as the most comprehensive treatment of the writings on the subject during these years. Building on the historic 1948 essay (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   507 citations  
  • The Philosophical Grammar of Scientific Practice.Hasok Chang - 2011 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (3):205-221.
    I seek to provide a systematic and comprehensive framework for the description and analysis of scientific practice—a philosophical grammar of scientific practice, ‘grammar’ as meant by the later Wittgenstein. I begin with the recognition that all scientific work, including pure theorizing, consists of actions, of the physical, mental, and ‘paper-and-pencil’ varieties. When we set out to see what it is that one actually does in scientific work, the following set of questions naturally emerge: who is doing what, why, and how? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Symposium: Communication and Verification.L. S. Stebbing, L. J. Russell & A. E. Heath - 1934 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 13 (1):159 - 202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1344 citations  
  • The philosophy of science.Stephen Toulmin - 1953 - New York,: Hutchinson's University Library.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Mr. Strawson on referring.Bertrand Russell - 1957 - Mind 66 (263):385-389.
    Leaving detail aside, I think we may sum up Mr. Strawson's argument and my reply to it as follows: There are two problems, that of descriptions and that of egocentricity. Mr. Strawson thinks they are one and the same problem, but it is obvious from his discussion that he has not considered as many kinds of descriptive phrases as are relevant to the argument. Having confused the two problems, he asserts dogmatically that it is only the egocentric problem that needs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • A theory of measurement.Herbert Dingle - 1950 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (1):5-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A plea for excuses.John Austin - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57:1--30.
    The subject of this paper, Excuses, is one not to be treated, but only to be introduced, within such limits. It is, or might be, the name of a whole branch, even a ramiculated branch, of philosophy, or at least of one fashion of philosophy. I shall try, therefore, first to state what the subject is, why it is worth studying, and how it may be studied, all this at a regrettably lofty level: and then I shall illustrate, in more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   266 citations  
  • Hempel on Scientific Understanding.Xingming Hu - 2021 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 88 (8):164-171.
    Hempel seems to hold the following three views: (H1) Understanding is pragmatic/relativistic: Whether one understands why X happened in terms of Explanation E depends on one's beliefs and cognitive abilities; (H2) Whether a scientific explanation is good, just like whether a mathematical proof is good, is a nonpragmatic and objective issue independent of the beliefs or cognitive abilities of individuals; (H3) The goal of scientific explanation is understanding: A good scientific explanation is the one that provides understanding. Apparently, H1, H2, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Explanation: Putting Communication First.Angela Potochnik - 2016 - Philosophy of Science 83 (5):721-732.
    Scientific explanations must bear the proper relationship to the world: they must depict what, out in the world, is responsible for the explanandum. But explanations must also bear the proper relationship to their audience: they must be able to create human understanding. With few exceptions, philosophical accounts of explanation either ignore entirely the relationship between explanations and their audience or else demote this consideration to an ancillary role. In contrast, I argue that considering an explanation’s communicative role is crucial to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • I.—A Plea for Excuses: The Presidential Address.J. L. Austin - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57 (1):1-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • The Road since Structure.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:3-13.
    A highly condensed account of the author's present view of some philosophical problems unresolved in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The concept of incommensurability, now considerably developed, remains at center stage, but the evolutionary metaphor, introduced in the final pages of the book, now also plays a principal role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • Communication and Verification.L. S. Stebbing, L. J. Russell & A. E. Heath - 1934 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 13 (1):159-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the Character of Philosophic Problems.Rudolf Carnap - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (1):5-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Two philosophies of science: A study in contrasts.Abraham S. Luchins & Edith H. Luchins - 1963 - Synthese 15 (1):292 - 316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On referring.Peter F. Strawson - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):320-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   618 citations  
  • Did Kuhn kill logical empiricism?George A. Reisch - 1991 - Philosophy of Science 58 (2):264-277.
    In the light of two unpublished letters from Carnap to Kuhn, this essay examines the relationship between Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and Carnap's philosophical views. Contrary to the common wisdom that Kuhn's book refuted logical empiricism, it argues that Carnap's views of revolutionary scientific change are rather similar to those detailed by Kuhn. This serves both to explain Carnap's appreciation of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and to suggest that logical empiricism, insofar as that program rested on Carnap's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • New philosophies of science in the USA.Theodore Kisiel & Galen Johnson - 1974 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 5 (1):138-191.
    The following overview of the present situation and recent trends in the philosophy of science in the USA brings together bibliographical and institutional evidence to document the last stages of the supersession of logical positivism, the emergence of the historical school , its widespread influence upon other fields as well as within philosophy of science, and finally some of the reactions to it, many of which envision their endeavors as mediations between the historical school and the older logical approaches As (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Logical Positivism and Analysis.L. Susan Stebbing - 1935 - Philosophical Review 44:605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Popper-Neurath debate and Neurath's attack on scientific method.Jordi Cat - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (2):219-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. V. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   619 citations  
  • Friedrich Waismann: The Open Texture of Analytic Philosophy.Thomas Uebel - forthcoming - Mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A New Look at Scientific Explanation.Mary Hesse - 1963 - Review of Metaphysics 17 (1):98 - 108.
    The first two volumes of the Minnesota Studies contained some of the classic accounts of this view, especially Carnap's "The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts," and Hempel's "The Theoretician's Dilemma," but even in these volumes anticipations of a change of view are discernible, in Sellars' "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind," Scriven's "Definitions, Explanations, and Theories," and Pap's excellent "Disposition Concepts and Extensional Logic," in which the adequacy of the empiricist's refuge in extensional logic is queried. Volume III contains two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The scientific outlook in 1851 and in 1951.Herbert Dingle - 1951 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 2 (6):85-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Must we mean what we say?Stanley Cavell - 1964 - In Vere Claiborne Chappell (ed.), Ordinary language: essays in philosophical method. New York: Dover Publications. pp. 172 – 212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • VI—Operational Coherence as the Source of Truth.Hasok Chang - 2017 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 117 (2):103-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Scientific Prediction in the Beginning of the “Historical Turn”: Stephen Toulmin and Thomas Kuhn.Wenceslao J. Gonzalez - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):351-357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Communication and Verification.L. S. Stebbing, L. J. Russell & A. E. Heath - 1934 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 13 (1):159-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Science. An Introduction.Michael Scriven & Stephen Toulmin - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Critical notices.Mary Hesse - 1963 - Mind 72 (287):429-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Vii.—Critical notices.Ernest Nagel - 1954 - Mind 63 (251):403-412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the character of philosophic problems.Rudolf Carnap - 1934 - Philosophy of Science 1 (1):5-19.
    Philosophers have ever declared that their problems lie at a different level from the problems of the empirical sciences. Perhaps one may agree with this assertion; the question is, however, where should one seek this level. The metaphysicians wish to seek their object behind the objects of empirical science; they wish to enquire after the essence, the ultimate cause of things. But the logical analysis of the pretended propositions of metaphysics has shown that they are not propositions at all, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations