Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Extended life.Ezequiel Di Paolo - 2008 - Topoi 28 (1):9-21.
    This paper reformulates some of the questions raised by extended mind theorists from an enactive, life/mind continuity perspective. Because of its reliance on concepts such as autopoiesis, the enactive approach has been deemed internalist and thus incompatible with the extended mind hypothesis. This paper answers this criticism by showing (1) that the relation between organism and cogniser is not one of co-extension, (2) that cognition is a relational phenomenon and thereby has no location, and (3) that the individuality of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  • The Virtual Other: Empathy in the Age of Virtuality.Thomas Fuchs - 2014 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 21 (5-6):152-173.
    In an age of growing virtual communication the question arises what role the human capacity of empathy plays in virtual relations. May empathy be detached from the immediate, embodied contact with others and be transferred to such relations? In order to answer this question, the paper distinguishes between primary, intercorporeal empathy and extended empathy which is based on the imaginative representation of the other, and fictional empathy which is directed to imagined or completely fictitious persons. The latter is characterized by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Non-objectal subjectivity.Manfred Frank - 2007 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (5-6):152-173.
    The immediate successors of Kant in classical German philosophy considered a subjectivity irreducible to objecthood as the core of personhood. The thesis of an irreducible subjectivity has, after the German idealists, been advocated by the phenomenological movement, as well as by analytical philosophers of self-consciousness such as Hector-Neri Castaneda and Sydney Shoemaker. Their arguments together show that self-consciousness cannot be reduced to a relation whereby a subject grasps itself as an object, but that there must be a core of subjectivity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   979 citations  
  • The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction?Shaun Gallagher - 2001 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (5-7):83-108.
    Theory of mind explanations of how we know other minds are limited in several ways. First, they construe intersubjective relations too narrowly in terms of the specialized cognitive abilities of explaining and predicting another person's mental states and behaviors. Second, they sometimes draw conclusions about secondperson interaction from experiments designed to test third-person observation of another's behavior. As a result, the larger claims that are sometimes made for theory of mind, namely, that theory of mind is our primary and pervasive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   240 citations  
  • The status and future of the Turing test.James H. Moor - 2001 - Minds and Machines 11 (1):77-93.
    The standard interpretation of the imitation game is defended over the rival gender interpretation though it is noted that Turing himself proposed several variations of his imitation game. The Turing test is then justified as an inductive test not as an operational definition as commonly suggested. Turing's famous prediction about his test being passed at the 70% level is disconfirmed by the results of the Loebner 2000 contest and the absence of any serious Turing test competitors from AI on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • ELIZA—a computer program for the study of natural language communication between man and machine.Joseph Weizenbaum - 1966 - Communications of the Acm 9 (1):36--45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Understanding A.I. — Can and Should we Empathize with Robots?Susanne Schmetkamp - 2020 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 11 (4):881-897.
    Expanding the debate about empathy with human beings, animals, or fictional characters to include human-robot relationships, this paper proposes two different perspectives from which to assess the scope and limits of empathy with robots: the first is epistemological, while the second is normative. The epistemological approach helps us to clarify whether we can empathize with artificial intelligence or, more precisely, with social robots. The main puzzle here concerns, among other things, exactly what it is that we empathize with if robots (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mutual Recognition in Human-Robot Interaction: a Deflationary Account.Ingar Brinck & Christian Balkenius - 2020 - Philosophy and Technology 33 (1):53-70.
    Mutually adaptive interaction involves the robot as a partner as opposed to a tool, and requires that the robot is susceptible to similar environmental cues and behavior patterns as humans are. Recognition, or the acknowledgement of the other as individual, is fundamental to mutually adaptive interaction between humans. We discuss what recognition involves and its behavioral manifestations, and describe the benefits of implementing it in HRI.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Could robots be phenomenally conscious?Frank Hofmann - 2018 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (3):579-590.
    In a recent book (Tye 2017), Michael Tye argues that we have reason to attribute phenomenal consciousness to functionally similar robots like commander Data of Star Trek. He relies on a kind of inference to the best explanation – ‘Newton’s Rule’, as he calls it. I will argue that Tye’s liberal view of consciousness attribution fails for two reasons. First, it leads into an inconsistency in consciousness attributions. Second, and even more importantly, it fails because ceteris is not paribus. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Folk-Psychological Interpretation of Human vs. Humanoid Robot Behavior: Exploring the Intentional Stance toward Robots.Sam Thellman, Annika Silvervarg & Tom Ziemke - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • You, Me, and We: The Sharing of Emotional Experiences.D. Zahavi - 2015 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 22 (1-2):84-101.
    When surveying recent philosophical work on the nature and status of collective intentionality and we-intentions, it is striking how much effort is spent on analysing the structure of joint action and on establishing whether or not the intention to, say, go for a walk or paint a house together is reducible to some form of I-intentionality. Much less work has been devoted to an analysis of shared affects and emotions. This is regrettable, not only because emotional sharing in all likelihood (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The phenomenon of life, toward a philosophical biology.Hans Jonas - 1966 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 160:494-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Making sense by making sentient: Effectance motivation increases anthropomorphism.Adam Waytz, Carey K. Morewedge, Nicholas Epley, George Monteleone, Jia-Hong Gao & John T. Cacioppo - 2010 - Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 99 (3):410-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Circularity of the Embodied Mind.Thomas Fuchs - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Self–consciousness and Self–knowledge: On Some Difficulties with the Reduction of Subjectivity.Manfred Frank - 2002 - Constellations 9 (3):390-408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On seeing human: A three-factor theory of anthropomorphism.Nicholas Epley, Adam Waytz & John T. Cacioppo - 2007 - Psychological Review 114 (4):864-886.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • The Theory of Meaning.Jakob von Uexküll - 1982 - Semiotica 42 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Thinking about consciousness: Phenomenological perspectives.Dan Zahavi - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The political choreography of the Sophia robot: beyond robot rights and citizenship to political performances for the social robotics market.Jaana Parviainen & Mark Coeckelbergh - forthcoming - AI and Society.
    A humanoid robot named ‘Sophia’ has sparked controversy since it has been given citizenship and has done media performances all over the world. The company that made the robot, Hanson Robotics, has touted Sophia as the future of artificial intelligence. Robot scientists and philosophers have been more pessimistic about its capabilities, describing Sophia as a sophisticated puppet or chatbot. Looking behind the rhetoric about Sophia’s citizenship and intelligence and going beyond recent discussions on the moral status or legal personhood of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • We need to talk about deception in social robotics!Amanda Sharkey & Noel Sharkey - 2020 - Ethics and Information Technology 23 (3):309-316.
    Although some authors claim that deception requires intention, we argue that there can be deception in social robotics, whether or not it is intended. By focusing on the deceived rather than the deceiver, we propose that false beliefs can be created in the absence of intention. Supporting evidence is found in both human and animal examples. Instead of assuming that deception is wrong only when carried out to benefit the deceiver, we propose that deception in social robotics is wrong when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Could robots be phenomenally conscious?Frank Hofmann - 2017 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (3):1-12.
    In a recent book, Michael Tye argues that we have reason to attribute phenomenal consciousness to functionally similar robots like commander Data of Star Trek. He relies on a kind of inference to the best explanation – ‘Newton’s Rule’, as he calls it. I will argue that Tye’s liberal view of consciousness attribution fails for two reasons. First, it leads into an inconsistency in consciousness attributions. Second, and even more importantly, it fails because ceteris is not paribus. The big, categorical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation.Dan Zahavi - 1999 - The Personalist Forum 15 (2):444-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   284 citations  
  • A stroll through the worlds of robots and animals: Applying Jakob von Uexkülls theory of meaning to adaptive robots and artificial life.Tom Ziemke & Noel E. Sharkey - 2001 - Semiotica 2001 (134).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Problem of Meaning in AI and Robotics: Still with Us after All These Years.Tom Froese & Shigeru Taguchi - 2019 - Philosophies 4 (2):14.
    In this essay we critically evaluate the progress that has been made in solving the problem of meaning in artificial intelligence (AI) and robotics. We remain skeptical about solutions based on deep neural networks and cognitive robotics, which in our opinion do not fundamentally address the problem. We agree with the enactive approach to cognitive science that things appear as intrinsically meaningful for living beings because of their precarious existence as adaptive autopoietic individuals. But this approach inherits the problem of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mutual Recognition in Human-Robot Interaction: a Deflationary Account.Ingar Brinck & Christian Balkenius - 2018 - Philosophy and Technology 1 (1):53-70.
    Mutually adaptive interaction involves the robot as a partner as opposed to a tool, and requires that the robot is susceptible to similar environmental cues and behavior patterns as humans are. Recognition, or the acknowledgement of the other as individual, is fundamental to mutually adaptive interaction between humans. We discuss what recognition involves and its behavioral manifestations, and describe the benefits of implementing it in HRI.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The social life of voices: studying the neural bases for the expression and perception of the self and others during spoken communication.Carolyn McGettigan - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The origins of social emotions and self-regulation in toddlerhood: New evidence.Karen Caplovitz Barrett - 2005 - Cognition and Emotion 19 (7):953-979.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Strange Order of Things: Life, Feeling, and the Making of Cultures.[author unknown] - 2018
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • A Pragmatic Approach to the Intentional Stance Semantic, Empirical and Ethical Considerations for the Design of Artificial Agents.Guglielmo Papagni & Sabine Koeszegi - 2021 - Minds and Machines 31 (4):505-534.
    Artificial agents are progressively becoming more present in everyday-life situations and more sophisticated in their interaction affordances. In some specific cases, like Google Duplex, GPT-3 bots or Deep Mind’s AlphaGo Zero, their capabilities reach or exceed human levels. The use contexts of everyday life necessitate making such agents understandable by laypeople. At the same time, displaying human levels of social behavior has kindled the debate over the adoption of Dennett’s ‘intentional stance’. By means of a comparative analysis of the literature (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Mass-Produced Sociable Humanoid Robot: Pepper: The First Machine of Its Kind.Amit Kumar Pandey & Rodolphe Gelin - 2018 - IEEE Robotics and Automation Magazine 25 (3):40-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations