Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2388 citations  
  • The Will to believe and other Essays in popular philosophy.William James - 1899 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 47:223-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations  
  • Words and Life.Hilary Putnam & James Conant - 1994 - Philosophy 70 (273):460-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce: Pragmatism and pragmaticism and Scientific metaphysics.Charles Sanders Peirce - 1960 - Cambridge: Belknap Press.
    Charles Sanders Peirce has been characterized as the greatest American philosophic genius. He is the creator of pragmatism and one of the founders of modern logic. James, Royce, Schroder, and Dewey have acknowledged their great indebtedness to him. A laboratory scientist, he made notable contributions to geodesy, astronomy, psychology, induction, probability, and scientific method. He introduced into modern philosophy the doctrine of scholastic realism, developed the concepts of chance, continuity, and objective law, and showed the philosophical significance of the theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   516 citations  
  • Essays in Radical Empiricism.B. H. Bode, William James & R. B. Perry - 1912 - Philosophical Review 21 (6):704.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Stance, feeling and phenomenology.Matthew Ratcliffe - 2011 - Synthese 178 (1):121-130.
    This paper addresses Bas van Fraassen’s claim that empiricism is a ‘stance’. I begin by distinguishing two different kinds of stance: an explicit epistemic policy and an implicit way of ‘finding oneself in a world’. At least some of van Fraassen’s claims, I suggest, refer to the latter. In explicating his ordinarily implicit ‘empirical stance’, he assumes the stance of the phenomenologist, describing the structure of his commitment to empiricism without committing to it in the process. This latter stance does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Stance and rationality: a perspective.Darrell Patrick Rowbottom & Otávio Bueno - 2011 - Synthese 178 (1):1-5.
    We offer an overview of some ways of examining the connections between stance and rationality, by surveying recent work on four central topics: the very idea of a stance, the relations between stances and voluntarism, the metaphysics and epistemology that emerge once stances are brought to center stage, and the role that emotions and phenomenology play in the empirical stance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Happiness, Completeness, and Indifference to Death in Epicurean Ethical Theory.Glenn Lesses - 2002 - Apeiron 35 (4):57-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Happiness and Death in Epicurean Ethics.Phillip Mitsis - 2002 - Apeiron 35 (4):41-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Moral Dimension of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Method.Chrysoula Gitsoulis - 2007 - Analysis and Metaphysics (Special Issue on Wittgenstein) 6:452-467.
    Wittgenstein wrote: 'Working in philosophy … is really more a working on oneself. On one's own interpretation. On one's own way of seeing things.' In what sense, for Wittgenstein, is work in philosophy 'work on oneself'? This paper will be devoted to answering this question, and to delineating the moral aspects of this work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to practise philosophy as therapy: Philosophical therapy and therapeutic philosophy.Eugen Fischer - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (1-2):49-82.
    Abstract: The notion that philosophy can be practised as a kind of therapy has become a focus of debate. This article explores how philosophy can be practised literally as a kind of therapy, in two very different ways: as philosophical therapy that addresses “real-life problems” (e.g., Sextus Empiricus) and as therapeutic philosophy that meets a need for therapy which arises in and from philosophical reflection (e.g., Wittgenstein). With the help of concepts adapted from cognitive and clinical psychology, and from cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Diseases of the Understanding and the Need for Philosophical Therapy.Eugen Fischer - 2010 - Philosophical Investigations 34 (1):22-54.
    The paper develops and addresses a major challenge for therapeutic conceptions of philosophy of the sort increasingly attributed to Wittgenstein. To be substantive and relevant, such conceptions have to identify “diseases of the understanding” from which philosophers suffer, and to explain why these “diseases” need to be cured in order to resolve or overcome important philosophical problems. The paper addresses this challenge in three steps: With the help of findings and concepts from cognitive linguistics and cognitive psychology, it redevelops the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Pyrrhonist’s ἀταραξία and φιλανθρωπία.Diego E. Machuca - 2006 - Ancient Philosophy 26 (1):111-126.
    The purpose of the present paper is twofold. First, to examine what beliefs, if any, underlie (a) the Pyrrhonist’s desire for ataraxia and his account of how this state may be attained, and (b) his philanthropic therapy, which seeks to induce, by argument, ejpochv and ataraxia in the Dogmatists. Second, to determine whether the Pyrrhonist’s philanthropy and his search for and attainment of ataraxia are, as scholars have generally believed, essential aspects of his stance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1025 citations  
  • Exchange on "Truth as convenient friction".Richard Rorty & Huw Price - 2010 - In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism and Normativity. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Naturalism without representationalism.Huw Price - 2004 - In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism in question. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. pp. 71--88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Hegel's metaphysics: Changing the debate.James Kreines - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (5):466–480.
    There are two general approaches to Hegel’s theoretical philosophy which are broadly popular in recent work. Debate between them is often characterized, by both sides, as a dispute between those favoring a more traditional “metaphysical” approach and those favoring a newer “nonmetaphysical” approach. But I argue that the most important and compelling points made by both sides are actually independent of the idea of a “nonmetaphysical” interpretation of Hegel, which is itself simply unconvincing. The most promising directions for future research, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Hegel's critique of Kant's theoretical philosophy.Karl Ameriks - 1985 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (1):1-35.
    This paper analyzes hegel's critique of kant's theoretical philosophy in terms of three specific objections to kant's transcendental deduction (concerning the representation of the i, The necessity of the categories, And the problem of a preliminary epistemology) and three specific objections to kant's transcendental idealism (concerning the thing in itself, The antinomies, And other specific problems of the transcendental dialectic).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Metaphysics without Pre-Critical Monism: Hegel on Lower-Level Natural Kinds and the Structure of Reality.James Kreines - 2008 - Hegel Bulletin 29 (1-2):48-70.
    Recent debates about Hegel's theoretical philosophy are marked by a surprising lack of agreement, extending all the way down to the most basic question:what is Hegel talking about?On the one hand, proponents of ‘metaphysical’ interpretations generally read Hegel as aiming to articulate the overall structure or organisation of reality itself, and the nature of a highest or most fundamental being. Particularly influential is the idea that Hegel is reviving and modifying a form of Spinoza's metaphysical monism, according to which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Hegels Erbe.Christoph Halbig, Michael Quante & Ludwig Siep - 2005 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 67 (2):391-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation.Richard Bett - 2002 - Mind 111 (443):714-718.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Soul Doctors. [REVIEW]Richard Kraut - 1995 - Ethics 105 (3):613-625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Rereading Aristotle’s De interpretatione 16a3-8.Steven Di Mattei - 2006 - Ancient Philosophy 26 (1):1-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • XV*—Pragmatism.Hilary Putnam - 1995 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95:291-306.
    Hilary Putnam; XV*—Pragmatism, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 95, Issue 1, 1 June 1995, Pages 291–306, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Liberal Naturalism: The Curious Case of Hegel.Paul Giladi - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (2):248-270.
    My aim in this paper is to defend the claim that the absolute idealism of Hegel is a liberal naturalist position against Sebastian Gardner’s claim that it is not genuinely naturalistic, and also to defend the position of ‘liberal naturalism’ from Ram Neta’s charge that there is no logical space for it to occupy. By ‘liberal naturalism’, I mean a doctrine which is a non-reductive form of philosophical naturalism. Like Fred Beiser, I take the thesis of liberal naturalism to find (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Hegel's Account of Kant's Epistemology in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy'.G. Bird - 1987 - In Stephen Priest (ed.), Hegel's critique of Kant. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 65--76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The 25 Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction.Eckart Förster - 2012 - Harvard University Press.
    Kant declared that philosophy began in 1781 with his Critique of Pure Reason. In 1806 Hegel announced that it had been completed. Förster assesses the steps that led from Kant’s “beginning” to Hegel’s “end” and concludes that both Kant and Hegel were indeed right. His study reveals Goethe’s significant contribution to post-Kantian thinking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Academics versus Pyrrhonists, reconsidered.Gisela Striker - 2010 - In Richard Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Pragmatism, Metaphysical Quietism, and the Problem of Normativity.David Macarthur - 2008 - Philosophical Topics 36 (1):193-209.
    There has always existed in the world, and there will always continue to exist, some kind of metaphysics, and with it the dialectic that is natural to pure reason. It is therefore the first and most important task of philosophy to deprive metaphysics, once and for all, of its injurious influence, by attacking its errors at their source. - Kant CPR:B xxxi..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Grammatical therapy and the third Wittgenstein.Rom Harré - 2008 - Metaphilosophy 39 (4-5):484-491.
    Abstract: The argument for interpreting Wittgenstein's project as primarily therapeutic can be extended from the domain of intellectual pathologies that form the core of the Philosophical Investigations to the topics in On Certainty , carrying further Hutchinson's recent argument for the priority of therapy in Wittgenstein's project. In this article I discuss whether the line Hutchinson takes is extendable to the work of the Third Wittgenstein. For example, how does Wittgenstein's discussion of Moore's "refutation of idealism" in On Certainty work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations