Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Contraction and closure.David Ripley - 2015 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):131-138.
    In this paper, I consider the connection between consequence relations and closure operations. I argue that one familiar connection makes good sense of some usual applications of consequence relations, and that a largeish family of familiar noncontractive consequence relations cannot respect this familiar connection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kripke semantics for logics with BCK implication.Wendy MacCaull - 1996 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 25:41-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Light affine set theory: A naive set theory of polynomial time.Kazushige Terui - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (1):9 - 40.
    In [7], a naive set theory is introduced based on a polynomial time logical system, Light Linear Logic (LLL). Although it is reasonably claimed that the set theory inherits the intrinsically polytime character from the underlying logic LLL, the discussion there is largely informal, and a formal justification of the claim is not provided sufficiently. Moreover, the syntax is quite complicated in that it is based on a non-traditional hybrid sequent calculus which is required for formulating LLL.In this paper, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Logic without contraction as based on inclusion and unrestricted abstraction.Uwe Petersen - 2000 - Studia Logica 64 (3):365-403.
    On the one hand, the absence of contraction is a safeguard against the logical (property theoretic) paradoxes; but on the other hand, it also disables inductive and recursive definitions, in its most basic form the definition of the series of natural numbers, for instance. The reason for this is simply that the effectiveness of a recursion clause depends on its being available after application, something that is usually assured by contraction. This paper presents a way of overcoming this problem within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)The semantics ofr.Edwin D. Mares & Robert K. Meyer - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1):95 - 110.
    The Logic R4 is obtained by adding the axiom □(A v B) → (◇A v □B) to the modal relevant logic NR. We produce a model theory for this logic and show completeness. We also show that there is a natural embedding of a Kripke model for S4 in each R4 model structure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Bad Worlds.Patrick Girard & Zach Weber - 2015 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):93-101.
    The idea of relevant logic—that irrelevant inferences are invalid—is appealing. But the standard semantics for relevant logics involve baroque metaphysics: a three-place accessibility relation, a star operator, and ‘bad’ worlds. In this article we propose that these oddities express a mismatch between non-classical object theory and classical metatheory. A uniformly relevant semantics for relevant logic is a better fit.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Is multiset consequence trivial?Petr Cintula & Francesco Paoli - 2016 - Synthese 199 (Suppl 3):741-765.
    Dave Ripley has recently argued against the plausibility of multiset consequence relations and of contraction-free approaches to paradox. For Ripley, who endorses a nontransitive theory, the best arguments that buttress transitivity also push for contraction—whence it is wiser for the substructural logician to go nontransitive from the start. One of Ripley’s allegations is especially insidious, since it assumes the form of a trivialisation result: it is shown that if a multiset consequence relation can be associated to a closure operator in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)L i D Z λ as a basis for PRA.Uwe Petersen - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (7):665-694.
    This paper is a sequel to my [7]. It focuses on the notion of natural number as introduced in section 11 of that paper with regard to forms of induction and recursive definitions. One point is that this notion of natural number is somewhat weaker than the classical one in so far as it is defined in terms of a weak implication. The other point is the lack of even a weak form of extensionality. As a main result of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Kripke models for linear logic.Gerard Allwein & J. Michael Dunn - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (2):514-545.
    We present a Kripke model for Girard's Linear Logic (without exponentials) in a conservative fashion where the logical functors beyond the basic lattice operations may be added one by one without recourse to such things as negation. You can either have some logical functors or not as you choose. Commutatively and associatively are isolated in such a way that the base Kripke model is a model for noncommutative, nonassociative Linear Logic. We also extend the logic by adding a coimplication operator, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Semantics of R4.Edwin D. Mares & Robert K. Meyer - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1):95-110.
    The Logic R4 is obtained by adding the axiom □ → to the modal relevant logic NR. We produce a model theory for this logic and show completeness. We also show that there is a natural embedding of a Kripke model for S4 in each R4 model structure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)The undecidability of grisin's set theory.Andrea Cantini - 2003 - Studia Logica 74 (3):345 - 368.
    We investigate a contractionless naive set theory, due to Grisin [11]. We prove that the theory is undecidable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Undecidability of Grisin's Set Theory.Andrea Cantini - 2003 - Studia Logica 74 (3):345-368.
    We investigate a contractionless naive set theory, due to Grisin [11]. We prove that the theory is undecidable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Kripke Models for Linear Logic.Allwein Gerard & Dunn J. Michael - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (2):514-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Logics without the contraction rule.Hiroakira Ono & Yuichi Komori - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):169-201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Kripke semantics for modal substructural logics.Norihiro Kamide - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (4):453-470.
    We introduce Kripke semantics for modal substructural logics, and provethe completeness theorems with respect to the semantics. Thecompleteness theorems are proved using an extended Ishihara's method ofcanonical model construction (Ishihara, 2000). The framework presentedcan deal with a broad range of modal substructural logics, including afragment of modal intuitionistic linear logic, and modal versions ofCorsi's logics, Visser's logic, Méndez's logics and relevant logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Toward useful type-free theories. I.Solomon Feferman - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1):75-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • What Is an Inconsistent Truth Table?Zach Weber, Guillermo Badia & Patrick Girard - 2016 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (3):533-548.
    ABSTRACTDo truth tables—the ordinary sort that we use in teaching and explaining basic propositional logic—require an assumption of consistency for their construction? In this essay we show that truth tables can be built in a consistency-independent paraconsistent setting, without any appeal to classical logic. This is evidence for a more general claim—that when we write down the orthodox semantic clauses for a logic, whatever logic we presuppose in the background will be the logic that appears in the foreground. Rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Observations on the Trivial World.Zach Weber & Hitoshi Omori - 2019 - Erkenntnis 84 (5):975-994.
    A world is trivial if it makes every proposition true all at once. Such a world is impossible, an absurdity. Our world, we hope, is not an absurdity. It is important, nevertheless, for semantic and metaphysical theories that we be able to reason cogently about absurdities—if only to see that they are absurd. In this note we describe methods for ‘observing’ absurd objects like the trivial world without falling in to incoherence, using some basic techniques from modal logic. The goal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Computation in Non-Classical Foundations?Toby Meadows & Zach Weber - 2016 - Philosophers' Imprint 16.
    The Church-Turing Thesis is widely regarded as true, because of evidence that there is only one genuine notion of computation. By contrast, there are nowadays many different formal logics, and different corresponding foundational frameworks. Which ones can deliver a theory of computability? This question sets up a difficult challenge: the meanings of basic mathematical terms are not stable across frameworks. While it is easy to compare what different frameworks say, it is not so easy to compare what they mean. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations