Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle’s Definition of Scientific Knowledge.Lucas Angioni - 2016 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 19 (1):79-104.
    In Posterior Analytics 71b9 12, we find Aristotle’s definition of scientific knowledge. The definiens is taken to have only two informative parts: scientific knowledge must be knowledge of the cause and its object must be necessary. However, there is also a contrast between the definiendum and a sophistic way of knowing, which is marked by the expression “kata sumbebekos”. Not much attention has been paid to this contrast. In this paper, I discuss Aristotle’s definition paying due attention to this contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Investigation of a Basic Logical Principle.Alan Code - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):341-357.
    Aristotle shares with Plato the attitude that the world, ‘the all,’ is a kosmos, a well-ordered and beautiful whole which, as such, can be rendered intelligible, or understood, by the intellect. One understands things, generally speaking, by tracing them back to their sources, origins or principles and causes or explanatory factors, and seeing in what manner they are related to these principles. We know, or understand, a thing when we grasp ‘the why’ or cause. Consequently, understanding is systematic. Some things (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle on Necessary Principles and on Explaining X through X’s essence.Lucas Angioni - 2014 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 7 (2):88-112.
    I discuss what Aristotle means when he say that scientific demonstration must proceed from necessary principles. I argue that, for Aristotle, scientific demonstration should not be reduced to sound deduction with necessary premises. Scientific demonstration ultimately depends on the fully appropriate explanatory factor for a given explanandum. This explanatory factor is what makes the explanandum what it is. Consequently, this factor is also unique. When Aristotle says that demonstration must proceed from necessary principles, he means that each demonstration requires the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Logical Atomism.Bertrand Russell - 1918 - In ¸ Iterussell1986. Open Court. pp. 193-210..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   335 citations  
  • Aristotle's Foundationalism.Breno Andrade Zuppolini - 2016 - Dissertatio 44:187-211.
    For Aristotle, demonstrative knowledge is the result of what he calls ‘intellectual learning’, a process in which the knowledge of a conclusion depends on previous knowledge of the premises. Since demonstrations are ultimately based on indemonstrable principles (the knowledge of which is called ‘νοῦς’), Aristotle is often described as advancing a foundationalist doctrine. Without disputing the nomenclature, I shall attempt to show that Aristotle’s ‘foundationalism’ should not be taken as a rationalist theory of epistemic justification, as if the first principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on per se accidents.Breno A. Zuppolini - 2018 - Ancient Philosophy 38 (1):113-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Why the Triangle has Two Right A ngles Kath' Hauto.J. E. Tiles - 1983 - Phronesis 28 (1):1 - 16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why the Triangle has Two Right A ngles Kath' Hauto.J. E. Tiles - 1983 - Phronesis 28 (1):1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Logical Atomism.Bertrand Russell - 1918 - The Monist 28 (4):495-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Definitions and Hypotheses in Posterior Analytics 72 a 19-25 and 76 b 35-77 a 4.Blake Landor - 1981 - Phronesis 26:308.
    In An. Post. I, 2, 72 a 8ff., Aristotle gives a description of the kinds of premisses that can occur in a demonstration. It is the purpose of this paper to explore some difficulties that arise in the interpretation of this passage and of the related passage at An. Post. I, 10, 76b 33 ff.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle on Demonstrating Essence.Blake Landor - 1985 - Apeiron 19 (2):116 - 132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Note on Commensurate Universals in the Posterior Analytics.Brad Inwood - 1979 - Phronesis 24 (3):320 - 329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Note on Commensurate Universals in the Posterior Analytics.Brad Inwood - 1979 - Phronesis 24 (3):320-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Differentia and the Per Se Accident in Aristotle.Herbert Granger - 1981 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 63 (2):118-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Atoms, complexes, and demonstration: Posterior analytics 96b15-25.Owen Goldin - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (4):707-727.
    There is agreement neither concerning the point that is being made in Posterior analytics 96b15–25 nor the issue Aristotle intends to address. There are two major lines of interpretation of this passage. According to one, sketched by Themistius and developed by Philoponus and Eustratius, Aristotle is primarily concerned with determining the definitions of the infimae species that fall under a certain genus. They understand Aristotle as arguing that this requires collating definitional predictions, seeing which are common to which species. Pacius, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Philosophy of Logical Atomism.Bertrand Russell - 1940 - Open Court. Edited by David Pears.
    THE PHILOSOPHY which I advocate is generally regarded as a species of realism, and accused of inconsistency because of the elements in it which seem contrary to that doctrine. For my part, I do not regard the issue between realists and their opponents as a funda- mental one; I could alter my view on this issue without changing my mind as to any of the doctrines upon which I wish to lay stress. I hold that logic is what is fundamental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   330 citations  
  • Interpreting Aristotle's Posterior analytics in late antiquity and beyond.Frans A. J. de Haas, Mariska Leunissen & Marije Martijn (eds.) - 2010 - Boston: Brill.
    This volume collects Late Ancient, Byzantine and Medieval appropriations of Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, addressing the logic of inquiry, concept formation, the question whether metaphysics is a science, and the theory of demonstration.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Causality and Coextensiveness in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 1.13.Lucas Angioni - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 54:159-185.
    I discuss an important feature of the notion of cause in Post. An. 1. 13, 78b13–28, which has been either neglected or misunderstood. Some have treated it as if Aristotle were introducing a false principle about explanation; others have understood the point in terms of coextensiveness of cause and effect. However, none offers a full exegesis of Aristotle's tangled argument or accounts for all of the text's peculiarities. My aim is to disentangle Aristotle's steps to show that he is arguing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Aristotle's Scientific Demonstrations as Expositions of Essence.Richard Tierney - 2001 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20:149-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations