Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Life and action: elementary structures of practice and practical thought.Michael Thompson - 2008 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Part I: The representation of life -- Can life be given a real definition? -- The representation of the living individual -- The representation of the life-form itself -- Part II: Naive action theory -- Types of practical explanation -- Naive explanation of action -- Action and time -- Part III: Practical generality -- Two tendencies in practical philosophy -- Practices and dispositions as sources of the goodness of individual actions -- Practice and disposition as sources of individual action.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   413 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy.Bernard Williams - 1985 - Ethics 97 (4):821-833.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   979 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy.Bernard Williams - 1987 - Behaviorism 15 (2):179-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   544 citations  
  • Engaging Reason.Joseph Raz - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (3):745-748.
    Joseph Raz presents a penetrating exploration of the interdependence of value, reason, and the will. These essays illuminate a wide range of questions concerning fundamental aspects of human thought and action. Engaging Reason is a summation of many years of original, compelling, and influential work by a major contemporary philosopher.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   254 citations  
  • Reasonably vicious.Candace Vogler - 2002 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Is unethical conduct necessarily irrational? Answering this question requires giving an account of practical reason, of practical good, and of the source or point of wrongdoing. By the time most contemporary philosophers have done the first two, they have lost sight of the third, chalking up bad action to rashness, weakness of will, or ignorance. In this book, Candace Vogler does all three, taking as her guides scholars who contemplated why some people perform evil deeds. In doing so, she sets (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review: On Virtue Ethics.Julia Driver - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):122.
    Rosalind Hursthouse has written an excellent book, in which she develops a neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics that she sees as avoiding some of the major criticisms leveled against virtue ethics in general, and against Aristotle's brand of virtue ethics in particular.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism.Robert L. Trivers - 1971 - Quarterly Review of Biology 46 (1):35-57.
    A model is presented to account for the natural selection of what is termed reciprocally altruistic behavior. The model shows how selection can operate -against the cheater (non-reciprocator) in the system. Three instances of altruistic behavior are discussed, the evolution of which the model can explain: (1) behavior involved in cleaning symbioses; (2) warning cries in birds: and (3) human reciprocal altruism. Regarding human reciprocal altruism, it is shown that the details of the psychological system that regulates this altruism can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   712 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Human Good in Aristotle.John M. Cooper - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (3):623-636.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Human Good in Aristotle.John M. Cooper - 1978 - Mind 87 (346):277-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Reason and Human Good in Aristotle.M. F. Burnyeat - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (1):102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • `Good' and `good for'.Thomas Hurka - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):71-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Role of Welfare in Eudaimonism.Anne Baril - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):511-535.
    Eudaimonists deny that eudaimonism is objectionably egoistic, but the way in which they do so commits them to eschewing an important insight that has been a central motivation for eudaimonism: the idea that an individual must, in the end, organize her life in such a way that it is good for her. In this paper I argue that the egoism objection prods eudaimonists to make a choice between (what we might roughly call) welfare-prior and excellence-prior eudaimonism, and I make some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Justice in Love.[author unknown] - 2011
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Virtue Ethics and the Nature and Forms of Egoism.Christopher Toner - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Research 35:275-303.
    Virtue ethics is often alleged to be egoistic, based upon its linking of virtue and happiness. Virtue ethicists often respond that their approach to the moral life is only “formally egoistic” and therefore not objectionable. This paper develops a clear, non-arbitrary definition of egoism (often lacking in these exchanges) as systematic pursuit of one’s own welfare, and then catalogues four broad egoistic strategies for achieving it. I identify “formal foundational egoism” as the one mostplausibly attributed to virtue ethics (its subtlety (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Human Morality.Gerald F. Gaus - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172):380-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Scotus on Morality and Nature.John Hare - 2000 - Medieval Philosophy & Theology 9 (1):15-38.
    This article is part of a larger project defending a version of divine command theory in ethics. What I am interested in from Scotus is that he combines such a theory with a view that grounds ethics in nature, especially human nature. In order to understand this combination, we need to start with his view of the two affections. Scotus takes from Anselm the idea that humans have in their will two basic affections (or intellectual appetites), what he calls the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Constructing a Good Life.Micah Lott - 2016 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 13 (3):363-375.
    _ Source: _Volume 13, Issue 3, pp 363 - 375 In _The Value of Living Well,_ Mark LeBar develops a position that he calls “virtue eudaimonism”. VE is both a eudaimonistic theory of practical reasoning and a constructivist account of the metaphysics of value. In this essay, I will explain the core of LeBar’s view and focus on two issues, one concerning VE ’s eudaimonism and the other concerning VE ’s constructivism. I will argue that, as it stands, VE does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Good For” supra “Good”.Sarah Stroud - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87 (2):459-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Human Morality by Samuel Scheffler. [REVIEW]Jonathan Lear - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):205-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations